4941 lines
304 KiB
Plaintext
4941 lines
304 KiB
Plaintext
The Myth Of Sisyphus
|
||
An Absurd Reasoning
|
||
Absurdity and Suicide
|
||
There is but one truly serious philosophical problem, and that
|
||
is suicide. Judging whether life is or is not worth living amounts to
|
||
answering the fundamental question of philosophy. All the rest—
|
||
whether or not the world has three dimensions, whether the mind
|
||
has nine or twelve categories—comes afterwards. These are
|
||
games; one must first answer. And if it is true, as Nietzsche claims,
|
||
that a philosopher, to deserve our respect, must preach by example,
|
||
you can appreciate the importance of that reply, for it will precede
|
||
the definitive act. These are facts the heart can feel; yet they call
|
||
for careful study before they become clear to the intellect.
|
||
If I ask myself how to judge that this question is more urgent
|
||
than that, I reply that one judges by the actions it entails. I have
|
||
never seen anyone die for the ontologi-cal argument. Galileo, who
|
||
held a scientific truth of great importance, abjured it with the
|
||
greatest ease as soon as it endangered his life. In a certain sense, he
|
||
did right.[1] That truth was not worth the stake. Whether the earth
|
||
or the sun revolves around the other is a matter of profound
|
||
indifference. To tell the truth, it is a futile question. On the other
|
||
hand, I see many people die because they judge that life is not
|
||
worth living. I see others paradoxically getting killed for the ideas
|
||
or illusions that give them a reason for living (what is called a
|
||
reason for living is also an excellent reason for dying). I therefore
|
||
conclude that the meaning of life is the most urgent of questions.
|
||
How to answer it? On all essential problems (I mean thereby those
|
||
that run the risk of leading to death or those that intensify the
|
||
passion of living) there are probably but two methods of thought:
|
||
the method of La Palisse and the method of Don Quixote. Solely
|
||
the balance between evidence and lyricism can allow us to achieve
|
||
simultaneously emotion and lucidity. In a subject at once so
|
||
humble and so heavy with emotion, the learned and classical
|
||
dialectic must yield, one can see, to a more modest attitude of mind
|
||
deriving at one and the same time from common sense and
|
||
understanding.
|
||
Suicide has never been dealt with except as a social
|
||
phenomenon. On the contrary, we are concerned here, at the outset,
|
||
with the relationship between individual thought and suicide. An
|
||
act like this is prepared within the silence of the heart, as is a great
|
||
work of art. The man himself is ignorant of it. One evening he
|
||
pulls the trigger or jumps. Of an apartment-building manager who
|
||
had killed himself I was told that he had lost his daughter five
|
||
years before, that be bad changed greatly since, and that that
|
||
experience had “undermined” him. A more exact word cannot be
|
||
imagined. Beginning to think is beginning to be undermined.
|
||
Society has but little connection with such beginnings. The worm
|
||
is in man’s heart. That is where it must be sought. One must follow
|
||
and understand this fatal game that leads from lucidity in the face
|
||
of existence to flight from light.
|
||
There are many causes for a suicide, and generally the most
|
||
obvious ones were not the most powerful. Rarely is suicide
|
||
committed (yet the hypothesis is not excluded) through reflection.
|
||
What sets off the crisis is almost always unverifiable. Newspapers
|
||
often speak of “personal sorrows” or of “incurable illness.” These
|
||
explanations are plausible. But one would have to know whether a
|
||
friend of the desperate man had not that very day addressed him
|
||
indifferently. He is the guilty one. For that is enough to precipitate
|
||
all the rancors and all the boredom still in suspension.[2]
|
||
But if it is hard to fix the precise instant, the subtle step when
|
||
the mind opted for death, it is easier to deduce from the act itself
|
||
the consequences it implies. In a sense, and as in melodrama,
|
||
killing yourself amounts to confessing. It is confessing that life is
|
||
too much for you or that you do not understand it. Let’s not go too
|
||
far in such analogies, however, but rather return to everyday
|
||
words. It is merely confessing that that “is not worth the trouble.”
|
||
Living, naturally, is never easy. You continue making the gestures
|
||
commanded by existence for many reasons, the first of which is
|
||
habit. Dying voluntarily implies that you have recognized, even
|
||
instinc—
|
||
tively, the ridiculous character of that habit, the absence of any
|
||
profound reason for living, the insane character of that daily
|
||
agitation, and the uselessness of suffering.
|
||
What, then, is that incalculable feeling that deprives the mind
|
||
of the sleep necessary to life? A world that can be explained even
|
||
with bad reasons is a familiar world. But, on the other hand, in a
|
||
universe suddenly divested of illusions and lights, man feels an
|
||
alien, a stranger. His exile is without remedy since he is deprived
|
||
of the memory of a lost home or the hope of a promised land. This
|
||
divorce between man and this life, the actor and his setting, is
|
||
properly the feeling of absurdity. All healthy men having thought
|
||
of their own suicide, it can be seen, without further explanation,
|
||
that there is a direct connection between this feeling and the
|
||
longing for death.
|
||
The subject of this essay is precisely this relationship between
|
||
the absurd and suicide, the exact degree to which suicide is a
|
||
solution to the absurd. The principle can be established that for a
|
||
man who does not cheat, what he believes to be true must
|
||
determine his action. Belief in the absurdity of existence must then
|
||
dictate his conduct. It is legitimate to wonder, clearly and without
|
||
false pathos, whether a conclusion of this importance requires
|
||
forsaking as rapidly as possible an incomprehensible condition. I
|
||
am speaking, of course, of men inclined to be in harmony with
|
||
themselves.
|
||
Stated clearly, this problem may seem both simple and
|
||
insoluble. But it is wrongly assumed that simple questions involve
|
||
answers that are no less simple and that evidence implies evidence.
|
||
A priori and reversing the terms of the problem, just as one does or
|
||
does not kill oneself, it seems that there are but two philosophical
|
||
solutions, either yes or no. This would be too easy. But allowance
|
||
must be made for those who, without concluding, continue
|
||
questioning. Here I am only slightly indulging in irony: this is the
|
||
majority. I notice also that those who answer “no” act as if they
|
||
thought “yes.” As a matter of fact, if I accept the Nietzschean
|
||
criterion, they think “yes” in one way or another. On the other
|
||
hand, it often happens that those who commit suicide were assured
|
||
of the meaning of life. These contradictions are constant. It may
|
||
even be said that they have never been so keen as on this point
|
||
where, on the contrary, logic seems so desirable. It is a
|
||
commonplace to compare philosophical theories and the behavior
|
||
of those who profess them. But it must be said that of the thinkers
|
||
who refused a meaning to life none except Kirilov who belongs to
|
||
literature, Peregrinos who is born of legend,[3] and Jules Lequier
|
||
who belongs to hypothesis, admitted his logic to the point of
|
||
refusing that life. Schopenhauer is often cited, as a fit subject for
|
||
laughter, because he praised suicide while seated at a well-set
|
||
table. This is no subject for joking. That way of not taking the
|
||
tragic seriously is not so grievous, but it helps to judge a man.
|
||
In the face of such contradictions and obscurities must we
|
||
conclude that there is no relationship between the opinion one has
|
||
about life and the act one commits to leave it? Let us not
|
||
exaggerate in this direction. In a man’s attachment to life there is
|
||
something stronger than all the ills in the world. The body’s
|
||
judgment is as good as the mind’s and the body shrinks from
|
||
annihilation. We get into the habit of living before acquiring the
|
||
habit of thinking. In that race which daily hastens us toward death,
|
||
the body maintains its irreparable lead. In short, the essence of that
|
||
contradiction lies in what I shall call the act of eluding because it is
|
||
both less and more than diversion in the Pascalian sense. Eluding is
|
||
the invariable game. The typical act of eluding, the fatal evasion
|
||
that constitutes the third theme of this essay, is hope. Hope of
|
||
another life one must “deserve” or trickery of those who live not
|
||
for life itself but for some great idea that will transcend it, refine it,
|
||
give it a meaning, and betray it.
|
||
Thus everything contributes to spreading confusion.
|
||
Hitherto, and it has not been wasted effort, people have played
|
||
on words and pretended to believe that refusing to grant a meaning
|
||
to life necessarily leads to declaring that it is not worth living. In
|
||
truth, there is no necessary common measure between these two
|
||
judgments. One merely has to refuse to he misled by the
|
||
confusions, divorces, and inconsistencies previously pointed out.
|
||
One must brush everything aside and go straight to the real
|
||
problem. One kills oneself because life is not worth living, that is
|
||
certainly a truth yet an unfruitful one because it is a truism. But
|
||
does that insult to existence, that flat denial in which it is plunged
|
||
come from the fact that it has no meaning? Does its absurdity
|
||
require one to escape it through hope or suicide—this is what must
|
||
be clarified, hunted down, and elucidated while brushing aside all
|
||
the rest. Does the Absurd dictate death? This problem must be
|
||
given priority over others, outside all methods of thought and all
|
||
exercises of the disinterested mind. Shades of meaning,
|
||
contradictions, the psychology that an “objective” mind can always
|
||
introduce into all problems have no place in this pursuit and this
|
||
passion. It calls simply for an unjust—in other words, logical—
|
||
thought. That is not easy. It is always easy to be logical. It is
|
||
almost impossible to be logical to the bitter end. Men who die by
|
||
their own hand consequently follow to its conclusion their
|
||
emotional inclination. Reflection on suicide gives me an
|
||
opportunity to raise the only problem to interest me: is there a logic
|
||
to the point of death? I cannot know unless I pursue, without
|
||
reckless passion, in the sole light of evidence, the reasoning of
|
||
which I am here suggesting the source. This is what I call an
|
||
absurd reasoning. Many have begun it. I do not yet know whether
|
||
or not they kept to it.
|
||
When Karl Jaspers, revealing the impossibility of constituting
|
||
the world as a unity, exclaims: “This limitation leads me to myself,
|
||
where I can no longer withdraw behind an objective point of view
|
||
that I am merely representing, where neither I myself nor the
|
||
existence of others can any longer become an object for me,” he is
|
||
evoking after many others those waterless deserts where thought
|
||
reaches its confines. After many others, yes indeed, but how eager
|
||
they were to get out of them! At that last crossroad where thought
|
||
hesitates, many men have arrived and even some of the humblest.
|
||
They then abdicated what was most precious to them, their life.
|
||
Others, princes of the mind, abdicated likewise, but they initiated
|
||
the suicide of their thought in its purest revolt. The real effort is to
|
||
stay there, rather, in so far as that is possible, and to examine
|
||
closely the odd vegetation of those distant regions. Tenacity and
|
||
acumen are privileged spectators of this inhuman show in which
|
||
absurdity, hope, and death carry on their dialogue. The mind can
|
||
then analyze the figures of that elementary yet subtle dance before
|
||
illustrating them and reliving them itself.
|
||
Absurd Walls
|
||
Like great works, deep feelings always mean more than they
|
||
are conscious of saying. The regularity of an impulse or a repulsion
|
||
in a soul is encountered again in habits of doing or thinking, is
|
||
reproduced in consequences of which the soul itself knows
|
||
nothing. Great feelings take with them their own universe, splendid
|
||
or abject. They light up with their passion an exclusive world in
|
||
which they recognize their climate. There is a universe of jealousy,
|
||
of ambition, of selfishness, or of generosity. A universe in other
|
||
words, a metaphysic and an attitude of mind. What is true of
|
||
already specialized feelings will be even more so of emotions
|
||
basically as indeterminate, simultaneously as vague and as
|
||
“definite,” as remote and as “present” as those furnished us by
|
||
beauty or aroused by absurdity.
|
||
At any streetcorner the feeling of absurdity can strike any man
|
||
in the face. As it is, in its distressing nudity, in its light without
|
||
effulgence, it is elusive. But that very difficulty deserves reflection.
|
||
It is probably true that a man remains forever unknown to us and
|
||
that there is in him something irreducible that escapes us. But
|
||
practically I know men and recognize them by their behavior, by
|
||
the totality of their deeds, by the consequences caused in life by
|
||
their presence. Likewise, all those irrational feelings which offer
|
||
no purchase to analysis. I can define them practically, appreciate
|
||
them practically, by gathering together the sum of their
|
||
consequences in the domain of the intelligence, by seizing and
|
||
noting all their aspects, by outlining their universe. It is certain that
|
||
apparently, though I have seen the same actor a hundred times, I
|
||
shall not for that reason know him any better personally. Yet if I
|
||
add up the heroes he has personified and if I say that I know him a
|
||
little better at the hundredth character counted off, this will be felt
|
||
to contain an element of truth. For this apparent paradox is also an
|
||
apologue. There is a moral to it. It teaches that a man defines
|
||
himself by his make-believe as well as by his sincere impulses.
|
||
There is thus a lower key of feelings, inaccessible in the heart but
|
||
partially disclosed by the acts they imply and the attitudes of mind
|
||
they assume. It is clear that in this way I am defining a method.
|
||
But it is also evident that that method is one of analysis and not of
|
||
knowledge. For methods imply metaphysics; unconsciously they
|
||
disclose conclusions that they often claim not to know yet.
|
||
Similarly, the last pages of a book are already contained in the first
|
||
pages. Such a link is inevitable. The method defined here
|
||
acknowledges the feeling that all true knowledge is impossible.
|
||
Solely appearances can be enumerated and the climate make itself
|
||
felt.
|
||
Perhaps we shall be able to overtake that elusive feeling of
|
||
absurdity in the different but closely related worlds of intelligence,
|
||
of the art of living, or of art itself. The climate of absurdity is in the
|
||
beginning. The end is the absurd universe and that attitude of mind
|
||
which lights the world with its true colors to bring out the
|
||
privileged and implacable visage which that attitude has discerned
|
||
in it.
|
||
* * *
|
||
All great deeds and all great thoughts have a ridiculous
|
||
beginning. Great works are often born on a street-corner or in a
|
||
restaurant’s revolving door. So it is with absurdity. The absurd
|
||
world more than others derives its nobility from that abject birth.
|
||
In certain situations, replying “nothing” when asked what one is
|
||
thinking about may be pretense in a man. Those who are loved are
|
||
well aware of this. But if that reply is sincere, if it symbolizes that
|
||
odd state of soul in which the void be-comes eloquent, in which
|
||
the chain of daily gestures is broken, in which the heart vainly
|
||
seeks the link that will connect it again, then it is as it were the first
|
||
sign of absurdity.
|
||
It happens that the stage sets collapse. Rising, streetcar, four
|
||
hours in the office or the factory, meal, streetcar, four hours of
|
||
work, meal, sleep, and Monday Tuesday Wednesday Thursday
|
||
Friday and Saturday accord—
|
||
ing to the same rhythm—this path is easily followed most of
|
||
the time. But one day the “why” arises and everything begins in
|
||
that weariness tinged with amazement. “Begins”—this is
|
||
important. Weariness comes at the end of the acts of a mechanical
|
||
life, but at the same time it inaugurates the impulse of
|
||
consciousness. It awakens consciousness and provokes what
|
||
follows. What follows is the gradual return into the chain or it is
|
||
the definitive awakening. At the end of the awakening comes, in
|
||
time, the consequence: suicide or recovery. In itself weariness has
|
||
something sickening about it. Here, I must conclude that it is good.
|
||
For everything be-gins with consciousness and nothing is worth
|
||
anything except through it. There is nothing original about these
|
||
remarks. But they are obvious; that is enough for a while, during a
|
||
sketchy reconnaissance in the origins of the absurd. Mere
|
||
“anxiety,” as Heidegger says, is at the source of everything.
|
||
Likewise and during every day of an unillustrious life, time
|
||
carries us. But a moment always comes when we have to carry it.
|
||
We live on the future: “tomorrow,” “later on,” “when you have
|
||
made your way,” “you will understand when you are old enough.”
|
||
Such irrelevan-cies are wonderful, for, after all, it’s a matter of
|
||
dying. Yet a day comes when a man notices or says that he is
|
||
thirty. Thus he asserts his youth. But simultaneously he situates
|
||
himself in relation to time. He takes his place in it. He admits that
|
||
he stands at a certain point on a curve that he acknowledges having
|
||
to travel to its end. He belongs to time, and by the horror that
|
||
seizes him, he recognizes his worst enemy. Tomorrow, he was
|
||
longing for tomorrow, whereas everything in him ought to reject it.
|
||
That revolt of the flesh is the absurd.[4]
|
||
A step lower and strangeness creeps in: perceiving that the
|
||
world is “dense,” sensing to what a degree a stone is foreign and
|
||
irreducible to us, with what intensity nature or a landscape can
|
||
negate us. At the heart of all beauty lies something inhuman, and
|
||
these hills, the softness of the sky, the outline of these trees at this
|
||
very minute lose the illusory meaning with which we had clothed
|
||
them, henceforth more remote than a lost paradise. The primitive
|
||
hostility of the world rises up to face us across millennia, for a
|
||
second we cease to understand it because for centuries we have
|
||
understood in it solely the images and designs that we had at-
|
||
tributed to it beforehand, because henceforth we lack the power to
|
||
make use of that artifice. The world evades us because it becomes
|
||
itself again. That stage scenery masked by habit becomes again
|
||
what it is. It withdraws at a distance from us. Just as there are days
|
||
when under the familial face of a woman, we see as a stranger her
|
||
we had loved months or years ago, perhaps we shall come even to
|
||
desire what suddenly leaves us so alone. But the time has not yet
|
||
come. Just one thing: that denseness and that strangeness of the
|
||
world is the absurd.
|
||
Men, too, secrete the inhuman. At certain moments of lucidity,
|
||
the mechanical aspect of their gestures, their meaningless
|
||
pantomime makes silly everything that surrounds them. A man is
|
||
talking on the telephone behind a glass partition; you cannot hear
|
||
him, but you see his incomprehensible dumb show: you wonder
|
||
why he is alive. This discomfort in the face of man’s own
|
||
inhumanity, this incalculable tumble before the image of what we
|
||
are, this “nausea,” as a writer of today calls it, is also the absurd.
|
||
Likewise the stranger who at certain seconds comes to meet us in a
|
||
mirror, the familiar and yet alarming brother we encounter in our
|
||
own photographs is also the absurd.
|
||
I come at last to death and to the attitude we have toward it. On
|
||
this point everything has been said and it is only proper to avoid
|
||
pathos. Yet one will never be sufficiently surprised that everyone
|
||
lives as if no one “knew.” This is because in reality there is no
|
||
experience of death. Properly speaking, nothing has been
|
||
experienced but what has been lived and made conscious. Here, it
|
||
is barely possible to speak of the experience of others’ deaths. It is
|
||
a substitute, an illusion, and it never quite convinces us. That
|
||
melancholy convention cannot be persuasive. The horror comes in
|
||
reality from the mathematical aspect of the event. If time frightens
|
||
us, this is because it works out the problem and the solution comes
|
||
afterward. All the pretty speeches about the soul will have their
|
||
contrary convincingly proved, at least for a time. From this inert
|
||
body on which a slap makes no mark the soul has disappeared.
|
||
This elementary and definitive aspect of the adventure constitutes
|
||
the absurd feeling. Under the fatal lighting of that destiny, its
|
||
uselessness becomes evident. No code of ethics and no effort are
|
||
justifiable a priori in the face of the cruel mathematics that
|
||
command our condition.
|
||
Let me repeat: all this has been said over and over. I am
|
||
limiting myself here to making a rapid classification and to
|
||
pointing out these obvious themes. They run through all literatures
|
||
and all philosophies. Everyday conversation feeds on them. There
|
||
is no question of reinventing them. But it is essential to be sure of
|
||
these facts in order to be able to question oneself subsequently on
|
||
the primordial question. I am interested let me repeat again—not
|
||
go much in absurd discoveries as in their consequences. If one is
|
||
assured of these facts, what is one to conclude, how far is one to go
|
||
to elude nothing? Is one to die voluntarily or to hope in spite of
|
||
everything? Beforehand, it is necessary to take the same rapid
|
||
inventory on the plane of the intelligence.
|
||
***
|
||
The mind’s first step is to distinguish what is true from what is
|
||
false. However, as soon as thought reflects on itself, what it first
|
||
discovers is a contradiction. Useless to strive to be convincing in
|
||
this case. Over the centuries no one has furnished a clearer and
|
||
more elegant demonstration of the business than Aristotle: “The
|
||
often ridiculed consequence of these opinions is that they destroy
|
||
themselves. For by asserting that all is true we assert the truth of
|
||
the contrary assertion and consequently the falsity of our own
|
||
thesis (for the contrary assertion does not admit that it can be true).
|
||
And if one says that all is false, that assertion is itself false. If we
|
||
declare that solely the assertion opposed to ours is false or else that
|
||
solely ours is not false, we are nevertheless forced to admit an
|
||
infinite number of true or false judgments. For the one who
|
||
expresses a true assertion proclaims simultaneously that it is true,
|
||
and so on ad infinitum.”
|
||
This vicious circle is but the first of a series in which the mind
|
||
that studies itself gets lost in a giddy whirling. The very simplicity
|
||
of these paradoxes makes them irreducible. Whatever may be the
|
||
plays on words and the acrobatics of logic, to understand is, above
|
||
all, to unify. The mind’s deepest desire, even in its most elaborate
|
||
operations, parallels man’s unconscious feeling in the face of his
|
||
universe: it is an insistence upon familiarity, an appetite for clarity.
|
||
Understanding the world for a man is reducing it to the human,
|
||
stamping it with his seal. The cat’s universe is not the universe of
|
||
the anthill. The truism “All thought is anthropomorphic” has no
|
||
other meaning. Likewise, the mind that aims to understand reality
|
||
can consider itself satisfied only by reducing it to terms of thought.
|
||
If man realized that the universe like him can love and suffer, he
|
||
would be reconciled. If thought discovered in the shimmering
|
||
mirrors of phenomena eternal relations capable of summing them
|
||
up and summing themselves up in a single principle, then would be
|
||
seen an intellectual joy of which the myth of the blessed would be
|
||
but a ridiculous imitation. That nostalgia for unity, that appetite for
|
||
the absolute illustrates the essential impulse of the human drama.
|
||
But the fact of that nostalgia’s existence does not imply that it is to
|
||
be immediately satisfied. For if, bridging the gulf that separates
|
||
desire from conquest, we assert with Parmenides the reality of the
|
||
One (whatever it may be), we fall into the ridiculous contradiction
|
||
of a mind that asserts total unity and proves by its very assertion its
|
||
own difference and the diversity it claimed to resolve. This other
|
||
vicious circle is enough to stifle our hopes.
|
||
These are again truisms. I shall again repeat that they are not
|
||
interesting in themselves but in the consequences that can be
|
||
deduced from them. I know another truism: it tells me that man is
|
||
mortal. One can nevertheless count the minds that have deduced
|
||
the extreme conclusions from it. It is essential to consider as a
|
||
constant point of reference in this essay the regular hiatus between
|
||
what we fancy we know and what we really know, practical assent
|
||
and simulated ignorance which allows us to live with ideas which,
|
||
if we truly put them to the test, ought to upset our whole life. Faced
|
||
with this inextricable contradiction of the mind, we shall fully
|
||
grasp the divorce separating us from our own creations. So long as
|
||
the mind keeps silent in the motionless world of its hopes,
|
||
everything is reflected and arranged in the unity of its nostalgia.
|
||
But with its first move this world cracks and tumbles: an infinite
|
||
number of shimmering fragments is offered to the understanding.
|
||
We must despair of ever reconstructing the familiar, calm surface
|
||
which would give us peace of heart. After so many centuries of
|
||
inquiries, so many abdications among thinkers, we are well aware
|
||
that this is true for all our knowledge. With the exception of
|
||
professional rationalists, today people despair of true knowledge. If
|
||
the only significant history of human thought were to be written, it
|
||
would have to be the history of its successive regrets and its
|
||
impotences.
|
||
Of whom and of what indeed can I say: “I know that!” This
|
||
heart within me I can feel, and I judge that it exists. This world I
|
||
can touch, and I likewise judge that it exists. There ends all my
|
||
knowledge, and the rest is construction. For if I try to seize this self
|
||
of which I feel sure, if I try to define and to summarize it, it is
|
||
nothing but water slipping through my fingers. I can sketch one by
|
||
one all the aspects it is able to assume, all those likewise that have
|
||
been attributed to it, this upbringing, this origin, this ardor or these
|
||
silences, this nobility or this vileness. But aspects cannot be added
|
||
up. This very heart which is mine will forever remain indefinable
|
||
to me. Between the certainty I have of my existence and the
|
||
content I try to give to that assurance, the gap will never be filled.
|
||
Forever I shall be a stranger to myself. In psychology as in logic,
|
||
there are truths but no truth. Socrates’”Know thyself” has as much
|
||
value as the “Be virtuous” of our confessionals. They reveal a
|
||
nostalgia at the same time as an ignorance. They are sterile
|
||
exercises on great subjects. They are legitimate only in precisely so
|
||
far as they are approximate.
|
||
And here are trees and I know their gnarled surface, water and
|
||
I feel its taste. These scents of grass and stars at night, certain
|
||
evenings when the heart relaxes—how shall I negate this world
|
||
whose power and strength I feel? Yet all the knowledge on earth
|
||
will give me nothing to assure me that this world is mine. You
|
||
describe it to me and you teach me to classify it. You enumerate its
|
||
laws and in my thirst for knowledge I admit that they are true. You
|
||
take apart its mechanism and my hope increases. At the final stage
|
||
you teach me that this wondrous and multicolored universe can be
|
||
reduced to the atom and that the atom itself can be reduced to the
|
||
electron. All this is good and I wait for you to continue. But you
|
||
tell me of an invisible planetary system in which electrons
|
||
gravitate around a nucleus. You explain this world to me with an
|
||
image. I realize then that you have been reduced to poetry: I shall
|
||
never know. Have I the time to become indignant? You have
|
||
already changed theories. So that science that was to teach me
|
||
everything ends up in a hypothesis, that lucidity founders in
|
||
metaphor, that uncertainty is resolved in a work of art. What need
|
||
had I of so many efforts? The soft lines of these hills and the hand
|
||
of evening on this troubled heart teach me much more. I have
|
||
returned to my beginning. I realize that if through science I can
|
||
seize phenomena and enumerate them, I cannot, for all that,
|
||
apprehend the world. Were I to trace its entire relief with my
|
||
finger, I should not know any more. And you give me the choice
|
||
between a description that is sure but that teaches me nothing and
|
||
hypotheses that claim to teach me but that are not sure. A stranger
|
||
to myself and to the world, armed solely with a thought that
|
||
negates itself as soon as it asserts, what is this condition in which I
|
||
can have peace only by refusing to know and to live, in which the
|
||
appetite for conquest bumps into walls that defy its assaults? To
|
||
will is to stir up paradoxes. Everything is ordered in such a way as
|
||
to bring into being that poisoned peace produced by
|
||
thoughtlessness, lack of heart, or fatal renunciations.
|
||
Hence the intelligence, too, tells me in its way that this world is
|
||
absurd. Its contrary, blind reason, may well claim that all is clear; I
|
||
was waiting for proof and longing for it to be right. But despite so
|
||
many pretentious centuries and over the heads of so many eloquent
|
||
and persuasive men, I know that is false. On this plane, at least,
|
||
there is no happiness if I cannot know. That universal reason,
|
||
practical or ethical, that determinism, those categories that explain
|
||
everything are enough to make a decent man laugh. They have
|
||
nothing to do with the mind. They negate its profound truth, which
|
||
is to be enchained. In this unintelligible and limited universe,
|
||
man’s fate henceforth assumes its meaning. A horde of irrationals
|
||
has sprung up and surrounds him until his ultimate end. In his
|
||
recovered and now studied lucidity, the feeling of the absurd
|
||
becomes clear and definite. I said that the world is absurd, but I
|
||
was too hasty. This world in itself is not reasonable, that is all that
|
||
can be said. But what is absurd is the confrontation of this
|
||
irrational and the wild longing for clarity whose call echoes in the
|
||
human heart. The absurd depends as much on man as on the world.
|
||
For the moment it is all that links them together. It binds them one
|
||
to the other as only hatred can weld two creatures together. This is
|
||
all I can discern clearly in this measureless universe where my
|
||
adventure takes place. Let us pause here. If I hold to be true that
|
||
absurdity that determines my relationship with life, if I become
|
||
thoroughly imbued with that sentiment that seizes me in face of the
|
||
world’s scenes, with that lucidity imposed on me by the pursuit of
|
||
a science, I must sacrifice everything to these certainties and I must
|
||
see them squarely to be able to maintain them. Above all, I must
|
||
adapt my behavior to them and pursue them in all their
|
||
consequences. I am speaking here of decency. But I want to know
|
||
beforehand if thought can live in those deserts.
|
||
* * *
|
||
I already know that thought has at least entered those deserts.
|
||
There it found its bread. There it realized that it had previously
|
||
been feeding on phantoms. It justified some of the most urgent
|
||
themes of human reflection.
|
||
From the moment absurdity is recognized, it becomes a
|
||
passion, the most harrowing of all. But whether or not one can live
|
||
with one’s passions, whether or not one can accept their law,
|
||
which is to burn the heart they simultaneously exalt—that is the
|
||
whole question. It is not, however, the one we shall ask just yet. It
|
||
stands at the center of this experience. There will be time to come
|
||
back to it. Let us recognize rather those themes and those impulses
|
||
born of the desert. It will suffice to enumerate them. They, too, are
|
||
known to all today. There have always been men to defend the
|
||
rights of the irrational. The tradition of what may be called
|
||
humiliated thought has never ceased to exist. The criticism of
|
||
rationalism has been made so often that it seems unnecessary to
|
||
begin again. Yet our epoch is marked by the rebirth of those
|
||
paradoxical systems that strive to trip up the reason as if truly it
|
||
had always forged ahead. But that is not so much a proof of the
|
||
efficacy of the reason as of the intensity of its hopes. On the plane
|
||
of history, such a constancy of two attitudes illustrates the essential
|
||
passion of man torn between his urge toward unity and the clear
|
||
vision he may have of the walls enclosing him.
|
||
But never perhaps at any time has the attack on reason been
|
||
more violent than in ours. Since Zarathustra’s great outburst: “By
|
||
chance it is the oldest nobility in the world. I conferred it upon all
|
||
things when I proclaimed that above them no eternal will was
|
||
exercised,” since Kierkegaard’s fatal illness, “that malady that
|
||
leads to death with nothing else following it,” the significant and
|
||
tormenting themes of absurd thought have followed one another.
|
||
Or at least, and this proviso is of capital importance, the themes of
|
||
irrational and religious thought. From Jaspers to Heidegger, from
|
||
Kierkegaard to Che-stov, from the phenomenologists to Scheler,
|
||
on the logical plane and on the moral plane, a whole family of
|
||
minds related by their nostalgia but opposed by their methods or
|
||
their aims, have persisted in blocking the royal road of reason and
|
||
in recovering the direct paths of truth. Here I assume these
|
||
thoughts to be known and lived. Whatever may be or have been
|
||
their ambitions, all started out from that indescribable universe
|
||
where contradiction, antinomy, anguish, or impotence reigns. And
|
||
what they have in common is precisely the themes so far disclosed.
|
||
For them, too, it must be said that what matters above all is the
|
||
conclusions they have managed to draw from those discoveries.
|
||
That matters so much that they must be examined separately. But
|
||
for the moment we are concerned solely with their discoveries and
|
||
their initial experiments. We are concerned solely with noting their
|
||
agreement. If it would be presumptuous to try to deal with their
|
||
philosophies, it is possible and sufficient in any case to bring out
|
||
the climate that is common to them.
|
||
Heidegger considers the human condition coldly and
|
||
announces that that existence is humiliated. The only reality is
|
||
“anxiety” in the whole chain of beings. To the man lost in the
|
||
world and its diversions this anxiety is a brief, fleeting fear. But if
|
||
that fear becomes conscious of itself, it becomes anguish, the
|
||
perpetual climate of the lucid man “in whom existence is
|
||
concentrated.” This professor of philosophy writes without
|
||
trembling and in the most abstract language in the world that “the
|
||
finite and limited character of human existence is more primordial
|
||
than man himself.” His interest in Kant extends only to
|
||
recognizing the restricted character of his “pure Reason.” This is to
|
||
coincide at the end of his analyses that “the world can no longer
|
||
offer anything to the man filled with anguish.” This anxiety seems
|
||
to him so much more important than all the categories in the world
|
||
that he thinks and talks only of it. He enumerates its aspects:
|
||
boredom when the ordinary man strives to quash it in him and
|
||
benumb it; terror when the mind contemplates death. He too does
|
||
not separate consciousness from the absurd. The consciousness of
|
||
death is the call of anxiety and “existence then delivers itself its
|
||
own summons through the intermediary of consciousness.” It is the
|
||
very voice of anguish and it adjures existence “to return from its
|
||
loss in the anonymous They.” For him, too, one must not sleep, but
|
||
must keep alert until the consummation. He stands in this absurd
|
||
world and points out its ephemeral character. He seeks his way
|
||
amid these ruins.
|
||
Jaspers despairs of any ontology because he claims that we
|
||
have lost “naivete.” He knows that we can achieve nothing that
|
||
will transcend the fatal game of appearances. He knows that the
|
||
end of the mind is failure. He tarries over the spiritual adventures
|
||
revealed by history and pitilessly discloses the flaw in each system,
|
||
the illusion that saved everything, the preaching that hid nothing.
|
||
In this ravaged world in which the impossibility of knowledge is
|
||
established, in which everlasting nothingness seems the only
|
||
reality and irremediable despair seems the only attitude, he tries to
|
||
recover the Ariadne’s thread that leads to divine secrets.
|
||
Chestov, for his part, throughout a wonderfully monotonous
|
||
work, constantly straining toward the same truths, tirelessly
|
||
demonstrates that the tightest system, the most universal
|
||
rationalism always stumbles eventually on the irrational of human
|
||
thought. None of the ironic facts or ridiculous contradictions that
|
||
depreciate the reason escapes him. One thing only interests him,
|
||
and that is the exception, whether in the domain of the heart or of
|
||
the mind. Through the Dostoevskian experiences of the
|
||
condemned man, the exacerbated adventures of the Nietzschean
|
||
mind, Hamlet’s imprecations, or the bitter aristocracy of an Ibsen,
|
||
he tracks down, il-luminates, and magnifies the human revolt
|
||
against the irremediable. He refuses the reason its reasons and
|
||
begins to advance with some decision only in the middle of that
|
||
colorless desert where all certainties have become stones.
|
||
Of all perhaps the most engaging, Kierkegaard, for a part of his
|
||
existence at least, does more than discover the absurd, he lives it.
|
||
The man who writes: “The surest of stubborn silences is not to
|
||
hold one’s tongue but to talk” makes sure in the beginning that no
|
||
truth is absolute or can render satisfactory an existence that is
|
||
impossible in itself. Don Juan of the understanding, he multiplies
|
||
pseudonyms and contradictions, writes his Discourses of
|
||
Edification at the same time as that manual of cynical spiritualism,
|
||
The Diary of the Seducer. He refuses consolations, ethics, reliable
|
||
principles. As for that thorn he feels in his heart, he is careful not
|
||
to quiet its pain. On the contrary, he awakens it and, in the
|
||
desperate joy of a man crucified and happy to be so, he builds up
|
||
piece by piece—lucidity, refusal, make believe—a category of the
|
||
man possessed. That face both tender and sneering, those
|
||
pirouettes followed by a cry from the heart are the absurd spirit
|
||
itself grappling with a reality beyond its comprehension. And the
|
||
spiritual adventure that leads Kierkegaard to his beloved scandals
|
||
begins likewise in the chaos of an experience divested of its setting
|
||
and relegated to its original incoherence.
|
||
On quite a different plane, that of method, Husserl and the
|
||
phenomenologists, by their very extravagances, reinstate the world
|
||
in its diversity and deny the transcendent power of the reason. The
|
||
spiritual universe becomes incalculably enriched through them.
|
||
The rose petal, the milestone, or the human hand are as important
|
||
as love, desire, or the laws of gravity. Thinking ceases to be
|
||
unifying or making a semblance familiar in the guise of a major
|
||
principle. Thinking is learning all over again to see, to be attentive,
|
||
to focus consciousness; it is turning every idea and every image, in
|
||
the manner of Proust, into a privileged moment. What justifies
|
||
thought is its extreme consciousness. Though more positive than
|
||
Kierkegaard’s or Chestov’s, Husserl’s manner of proceeding, in
|
||
the beginning, nevertheless negates the classic method of the
|
||
reason, disappoints hope, opens to intuition and to the heart a
|
||
whole proliferation of phenomena, the wealth of which has about it
|
||
something inhuman. These paths lead to all sciences or to none.
|
||
This amounts to saying that in this case the means are more
|
||
important than the end. All that is involved is “an attitude for
|
||
understanding” and not a consolation. Let me repeat: in the
|
||
beginning, at very least.
|
||
How can one fail to feel the basic relationship of these minds!
|
||
How can one fail to see that they take their stand around a
|
||
privileged and bitter moment in which hope has no further place? I
|
||
want everything to be explained to me or nothing. And the reason
|
||
is impotent when it hears this cry from the heart. The mind aroused
|
||
by this insistence seeks and finds nothing but contradictions and
|
||
nonsense. What I fail to understand is nonsense. The world is
|
||
peopled with such irrationals. The world itself, whose single
|
||
meaning I do not understand, is but a vast irrational. If one could
|
||
only say just once: “This is clear,” all would be saved. But these
|
||
men vie with one another in proclaiming that nothing is clear, all is
|
||
chaos, that all man has is his lucidity and his definite knowledge of
|
||
the walls surrounding him.
|
||
All these experiences agree and confirm one another. The
|
||
mind, when it reaches its limits, must make a judgment and choose
|
||
its conclusions. This is where suicide and the reply stand. But I
|
||
wish to reverse the order of the inquiry and start out from the
|
||
intelligent adventure and come back to daily acts. The experiences
|
||
called to mind here were born in the desert that we must not leave
|
||
behind. At least it is essential to know how far they went. At this
|
||
point of his effort man stands face to face with the irrational. He
|
||
feels within him his longing for happiness and for reason. The
|
||
absurd is born of this confrontation between the human need and
|
||
the unreasonable silence of the world. This must not be forgotten.
|
||
This must be clung to because the whole consequence of a life can
|
||
depend on it. The irrational, the human nostalgia, and the absurd
|
||
that is born of their encounter—these are the three characters in the
|
||
drama that must necessarily end with all the logic of which an
|
||
existence is capable.
|
||
Philosophical Suicide
|
||
The feeling of the absurd is not, for all that, the notion of the
|
||
absurd. It lays the foundations for it, and that is all. It is not limited
|
||
to that notion, except in the brief moment when it passes judgment
|
||
on the universe. Subsequently it has a chance of going further. It is
|
||
alive; in other words, it must die or else reverberate. So it is with
|
||
the themes we have gathered together. But there again what
|
||
interests me is not works or minds, criticism of which would call
|
||
for another form and another place, but the discovery of what their
|
||
conclusions have in common. Never, perhaps, have minds been so
|
||
different. And yet we recognize as identical the spiritual
|
||
landscapes in which they get under way. Likewise, despite such
|
||
dissimilar zones of knowledge, the cry that terminates their
|
||
itinerary rings out in the same way. It is evident that the thinkers
|
||
we have just recalled have a common climate.
|
||
To say that that climate is deadly scarcely amounts to playing
|
||
on words. Living under that stifling sky forces one to get away or
|
||
to stay. The important thing is to find out how people get away in
|
||
the first case and why people stay in the second case. This is how I
|
||
define the problem of suicide and the possible interest in the
|
||
conclusions of existential philosophy.
|
||
But first I want to detour from the direct path. Up to now we
|
||
have managed to circumscribe the absurd from the outside. One
|
||
can, however, wonder how much is clear in that notion and by
|
||
direct analysis try to discover its meaning on the one hand and, on
|
||
the other, the consequences it involves.
|
||
If I accuse an innocent man of a monstrous crime, if I tell a
|
||
virtuous man that he has coveted his own sister, he will reply that
|
||
this is absurd. His indignation has its comical aspect. But it also
|
||
has its fundamental reason. The virtuous man illustrates by that
|
||
reply the definitive antinomy existing between the deed I am
|
||
attributing to him and his lifelong principles. “It’s absurd” means
|
||
“It’s impossible” but also “It’s contradictory.” If I see a man armed
|
||
only with a sword attack a group of machine guns, I shall consider
|
||
his act to be absurd. But it is so solely by virtue of the
|
||
disproportion between his intention and the reality he will
|
||
encounter, of the contradiction I notice between his true strength
|
||
and the aim he has in view. Likewise we shall deem a verdict
|
||
absurd when we contrast it with the verdict the facts apparently
|
||
dictated. And, similarly, a demonstration by the absurd is achieved
|
||
by comparing the consequences of such a reasoning with the
|
||
logical reality one wants to set up. In all these cases, from the
|
||
simplest to the most complex, the magnitude of the absurdity will
|
||
be in direct ratio to the distance between the two terms of my
|
||
comparison. There are absurd marriages, challenges, rancors,
|
||
silences, wars, and even peace treaties. For each of them the
|
||
absurdity springs from a comparison. I am thus justified in saying
|
||
that the feeling of absurdity does not spring from the mere scrutiny
|
||
of a fact or an impression, but that it bursts from the comparison
|
||
between a bare fact and a certain reality, between an action and the
|
||
world that transcends it. The absurd is essentially a divorce. It lies
|
||
in neither of the elements compared; it is born of their
|
||
confrontation.
|
||
In this particular case and on the plane of intelligence, I can
|
||
therefore say that the Absurd is not in man (if such a metaphor
|
||
could have a meaning) nor in the world, but in their presence
|
||
together. For the moment it is the only bond uniting them. If wish
|
||
to limit myself to facts, I know what man wants, I know what the
|
||
world offers him, and now I can say that I also know what links
|
||
them. I have no need to dig deeper. A single certainty is enough for
|
||
the seeker. He simply has to derive all the consequences from it.
|
||
The immediate consequence is also a rule of method. The odd
|
||
trinity brought to light in this way is certainly not a startling
|
||
discovery. But it resembles the data of experience in that it is both
|
||
infinitely simple and infinitely complicated. Its first distinguishing
|
||
feature in this regard is that it cannot be divided. To destroy one of
|
||
its terms is to destroy the whole. There can be no absurd outside
|
||
the human mind. Thus, like everything else, the absurd ends with
|
||
death. But there can be no absurd outside this world either. And it
|
||
is by this elementary criterion that I judge the notion of the absurd
|
||
to be essential and consider that it can stand as the first of my
|
||
truths. The rule of method alluded to above appears here. If I judge
|
||
that a thing is true, I must preserve it. If I attempt to solve a
|
||
problem, at least I must not by that very solution conjure away one
|
||
of the terms of the problem. For me the sole datum is the absurd.
|
||
The first and, after all, the only condition of my inquiry is to
|
||
preserve the very thing that crushes me, consequently to respect
|
||
what I consider essential in it. I have just defined it as a
|
||
confrontation and an unceasing struggle.
|
||
And carrying this absurd logic to its conclusion, I must admit
|
||
that that struggle implies a total absence of hope (which has
|
||
nothing to do with despair), a continual rejection (which must not
|
||
be confused with renunciation), and a conscious dissatisfaction
|
||
(which must not be compared to immature unrest). Everything that
|
||
destroys, conjures away, or exorcises these requirements (and, to
|
||
begin with, consent which overthrows divorce) ruins the absurd
|
||
and devaluates the attitude that may then be proposed. The absurd
|
||
has meaning only in so far as it is not agreed to.
|
||
***
|
||
There exists an obvious fact that seems utterly moral: namely,
|
||
that a man is always a prey to his truths. Once he has admitted
|
||
them, he cannot free himself from them. One has to pay something.
|
||
A man who has be-come conscious of the absurd is forever bound
|
||
to it. A man devoid of hope and conscious of being so has ceased
|
||
to belong to the future. That is natural. But it is just as natural that
|
||
he should strive to escape the universe of which he is the creator.
|
||
All the foregoing has significance only on account of this paradox.
|
||
Certain men, starting from a critique of rationalism, have admitted
|
||
the absurd climate. Nothing is more instructive in this regard than
|
||
to scrutinize the way in which they have elaborated their
|
||
consequences.
|
||
Now, to limit myself to existential philosophies, I see that all of
|
||
them without exception suggest escape. Through an odd reasoning,
|
||
starting out from the absurd over the ruins of reason, in a closed
|
||
universe limited to the human, they deify what crushes them and
|
||
find reason to hope in what impoverishes them. That forced hope is
|
||
religious in all of them. It deserves attention.
|
||
I shall merely analyze here as examples a few themes dear to
|
||
Chestov and Kierkegaard. But Jaspers will provide us, in
|
||
caricatural form, a typical example of this attitude. As a result the
|
||
rest will be clearer. He is left powerless to realize the transcendent,
|
||
incapab le of plumbing the depth of experience, and conscious of
|
||
that universe upset by failure. Will he advance or at least draw the
|
||
conclusions from that failure? He contributes nothing new. He has
|
||
found nothing in experience but the confession of his own
|
||
impotence and no occasion to infer any satisfactory principle. Yet
|
||
without justification, as he says to himself, he suddenly asserts all
|
||
at once the transcendent, the essence of experience, and the
|
||
superhuman significance of life when he writes: “Does not the
|
||
failure reveal, beyond any possible explanation and interpretation,
|
||
not the absence but the existence of transcendence?” That
|
||
existence which, suddenly and through a blind act of human
|
||
confidence, explains everything, he defines as “the unthinkable
|
||
unity of the general and the particular.” Thus the absurd becomes
|
||
god (in the broadest meaning of this word) and that inability to
|
||
understand becomes the existence that illuminates everything.
|
||
Nothing logically prepares this reasoning. I can call it a leap. And
|
||
para-doxically can be understood Jaspers’s insistence, his infinite
|
||
patience devoted to making the experience of the transcendent
|
||
impossible to realize. For the more fleeting that approximation is,
|
||
the more empty that definition proves to be, and the more real that
|
||
transcendent is to him; for the passion he devotes to asserting it is
|
||
in direct proportion to the gap between his powers of explanation
|
||
and the irrationality of the world and of experience. It thus appears
|
||
that the more bitterly Jaspers destroys the reason’s preconceptions,
|
||
the more radically he will explain the world. That apostle of
|
||
humiliated thought will find at the very end of humiliation the
|
||
means of regenerating being to its very depth.
|
||
Mystical thought has familiarized us with such devices. They
|
||
are just as legitimate as any attitude of mind. But for the moment I
|
||
am acting as if I took a certain problem seriously. Without judging
|
||
beforehand the general value of this attitude or its educative power,
|
||
I mean simply to consider whether it answers the conditions I set
|
||
myself, whether it is worthy of the conflict that concerns me. Thus
|
||
I return to Chestov. A commentator relates a remark of his that
|
||
deserves interest:
|
||
“The only true solution,” he said, “is precisely where human
|
||
judgment sees no solution. Otherwise, what need would we have of
|
||
God? We turn toward God only to obtain the impossible. As for
|
||
the possible, men suffice.” If there is a Chestovian philosophy, I
|
||
can say that it is altogether summed up in this way. For when, at
|
||
the conclusion of his passionate analyses, Chestov discovers the
|
||
fundamental absurdity of all existence, he does not say: “This is
|
||
the absurd,” but rather: “This is God: we must rely on him even if
|
||
he does not correspond to any of our rational categories.” So that
|
||
confusion may not be possible, the Russian philosopher even hints
|
||
that this God is perhaps full of hatred and hateful,
|
||
incomprehensible and contradictory; but the more hideous is his
|
||
face, the more he asserts his power. His greatness is his
|
||
incoherence. His proof is his inhumanity. One must spring into him
|
||
and by this leap free oneself from rational illusions. Thus, for
|
||
Chestov acceptance of the absurd is contemporaneous with the
|
||
absurd itself. Being aware of it amounts to accepting it, and the
|
||
whole logical effort of his thought is to bring it out so that at the
|
||
same time the tremendous hope it involves may burst forth. Let me
|
||
repeat that this attitude is legitimate. But I am persisting here in
|
||
considering a single problem and all its consequences. I do not
|
||
have to examine the emotion of a thought or of an act of faith. I
|
||
have a whole lifetime to do that. I know that the rationalist finds
|
||
Chestov’s attitude annoying. But I also feel that Chestov is right
|
||
rather than the rationalist, and I merely want to know if he remains
|
||
faithful to the commandments of the absurd.
|
||
Now, if it is admitted that the absurd is the contrary of hope, it
|
||
is seen that existential thought for Chestov presupposes the absurd
|
||
but proves it only to dispel it. Such subtlety of thought is a
|
||
conjuror’s emotional trick. When Chestov elsewhere sets his
|
||
absurd in opposition to current morality and reason, he calls it truth
|
||
and redemption. Hence, there is basically in that definition of the
|
||
absurd an approbation that Chestov grants it. If it is admitted that
|
||
all the power of that notion lies in the way it runs counter to our
|
||
elementary hopes, if it is felt that to remain, the absurd requires not
|
||
to be consented to, then it can be clearly seen that it has lost its true
|
||
aspect, its human and relative character in order to enter an eternity
|
||
that is both incomprehensible and satisfying. If there is an absurd,
|
||
it is in man’s universe. The moment the notion transforms itself
|
||
into eternity’s springboard, it ceases to be linked to human lucidity.
|
||
The absurd is no longer that evidence that man ascertains without
|
||
consenting to it. The struggle is eluded. Man integrates the absurd
|
||
and in that communion causes to disappear its essential character,
|
||
which is opposition, laceration, and divorce. This leap is an escape.
|
||
Chestov, who is so fond of quoting Hamlet’s remark: “The time is
|
||
out of joint,” writes it down with a sort of savage hope that seems
|
||
to belong to him in particular. For it is not in this sense that Hamlet
|
||
says it or Shakespeare writes it. The intoxication of the irrational
|
||
and the vocation of rapture turn a lucid mind away from the
|
||
absurd. To Chestov reason is useless but there is something beyond
|
||
reason. To an absurd mind reason is useless and there is nothing
|
||
beyond reason.
|
||
This leap can at least enlighten us a little more as to the true
|
||
nature of the absurd. We know that it is worthless except in an
|
||
equilibrium, that it is, above all, in the comparison and not in the
|
||
terms of that comparison. But it so happens that Chestov puts all
|
||
the emphasis on one of the terms and destroys the equilibrium. Our
|
||
appetite for understanding, our nostalgia for the absolute are
|
||
explicable only in so far, precisely, as we can understand and
|
||
explain many things. It is useless to negate the reason absolutely. It
|
||
has its order in which it is efficacious. It is properly that of human
|
||
experience. Whence we wanted to make everything clear. If we
|
||
cannot do so, if the absurd is born on that occasion, it is born
|
||
precisely at the very meeting-point of that efficacious but limited
|
||
reason with the ever resurgent irrational. Now, when Chestov rises
|
||
up against a Hegelian proposition such as “the motion of the solar
|
||
system takes place in conformity with immutable laws and those
|
||
laws are its reason,” when he devotes all his passion to upsetting
|
||
Spinoza’s rationalism, he concludes, in effect, in favor of the
|
||
vanity of all reason. Whence, by a natural and illegitimate reversal,
|
||
to the pre-eminence of the irrational.[5] But the transition is not
|
||
evident. For here may intervene the notion of limit and the notion
|
||
of level. The laws of nature may be operative up to a certain limit,
|
||
beyond which they turn against themselves to give birth to the
|
||
absurd. Or else, they may justify themselves on the level of
|
||
description without for that reason being true on the level of
|
||
explanation.
|
||
Everything is sacrificed here to the irrational, and, the demand
|
||
for clarity being conjured away, the absurd disappears with one of
|
||
the terms of its comparison. The absurd man, on the other hand,
|
||
does not undertake such a leveling process. He recognizes the
|
||
struggle, does not absolutely scorn reason, and admits the
|
||
irrational. Thus he again embraces in a single glance all the data of
|
||
experience and he is little inclined to leap before knowing. He
|
||
knows simply that in that alert awareness there is no further place
|
||
for hope.
|
||
What is perceptible in Leo Chestov will be perhaps even more
|
||
so in Kierkegaard. To be sure, it is hard to outline clear
|
||
propositions in so elusive a writer. But, despite apparently opposed
|
||
writings, beyond the pseudonyms, the tricks, and the smiles, can be
|
||
felt throughout that work, as it were, the presentiment (at the same
|
||
time as the apprehension) of a truth which eventually bursts forth
|
||
in the last works: Kierkegaard likewise takes the leap. His
|
||
childhood having been so frightened by Christianity, he ultimately
|
||
returns to its harshest aspect. For him, too, antinomy and paradox
|
||
become criteria of the religious. Thus, the very thing that led to
|
||
despair of the meaning and depth of this life now gives it its truth
|
||
and its clarity. Christianity is the scandal, and what Kierkegaard
|
||
calls for quite plainly is the third sacrifice required by Ignatius
|
||
Loyola, the one in which God most rejoices: “The sacrifice of the
|
||
intellect.” [6]
|
||
This effect of the “leap” is odd, but must not surprise us any
|
||
longer. He makes of the absurd the criterion of the other world,
|
||
whereas it is simply a residue of the experience of this world. “In
|
||
his failure,” says Kierkegaard, “the believer finds his triumph.”
|
||
It is not for me to wonder to what stirring preaching this
|
||
attitude is linked. I merely have to wonder if the spectacle of the
|
||
absurd and its own character justifies it. On this point, I know that
|
||
it is not so. Upon considering again the content of the absurd, one
|
||
understands better the method that inspired Kierkegaard. Between
|
||
the irrational of the world and the insurgent nostalgia of the absurd,
|
||
he does not maintain the equilibrium. He does not respect the
|
||
relationship that constitutes, properly speaking, the feeling of
|
||
absurdity. Sure of being unable to escape the irrational, he wants at
|
||
least to save himself from that desperate nostalgia that seems to
|
||
him sterile and devoid of implication. But if he may be right on
|
||
this point in his judgment, he could not be in his negation. If he
|
||
substitutes for his cry of revolt a frantic adherence, at once he is
|
||
led to blind himself to the absurd which hitherto enlightened him
|
||
and to deify the only certainty he henceforth possesses, the
|
||
irrational. The important thing, as Abbe Galiani said to Mme
|
||
d’Epinay, is not to be cured, but to live with one’s ailments.
|
||
Kierkegaard wants to be cured. To be cured is his frenzied wish,
|
||
and it runs throughout his whole journal. The entire effort of his
|
||
intelligence is to escape the antinomy of the human condition. An
|
||
all the more desperate effort since he intermittently perceives its
|
||
vanity when he speaks of himself, as if neither fear of God nor
|
||
piety were capable of bringing him to peace. Thus it is that,
|
||
through a strained subterfuge, he gives the irrational the
|
||
appearance and God the attributes of the absurd: unjust,
|
||
incoherent, and incomprehensible. Intelligence alone in him strives
|
||
to stifle the underlying demands of the human heart. Since nothing
|
||
is proved, everything can be proved.
|
||
Indeed, Kierkegaard himself shows us the path taken. I do not
|
||
want to suggest anything here, but how can one fail to read in his
|
||
works the signs of an almost intentional mutilation of the soul to
|
||
balance the mutilation accepted in regard to the absurd? It is the
|
||
leitmotiv of the Journal. “What I lacked was the animal which also
|
||
belongs to human destiny .... But give me a body then.” And
|
||
further on: “Oh! especially in my early youth what should I not
|
||
have given to be a man, even for six months ... what I lack,
|
||
basically, is a body and the physical conditions of existence.”
|
||
Elsewhere, the same man nevertheless adopts the great cry of hope
|
||
that has come down through so many centuries and quickened so
|
||
many hearts, except that of the absurd man. “But for the Christian
|
||
death is certainly not the end of everything and it implies infinitely
|
||
more hope than life implies for us, even when that life is
|
||
overflowing with health and vigor.” Reconciliation through
|
||
scandal is still reconciliation. It allows one perhaps, as can be seen,
|
||
to derive hope of its contrary, which is death. But even if fellow-
|
||
feeling inclines one toward that attitude, still it must be said that
|
||
excess justifies nothing. That transcends, as the saying goes, the
|
||
human scale; therefore it must be superhuman. But this “therefore”
|
||
is superfluous. There is no logical certainty here. There is no
|
||
experimental probability either. All I can say is that, in fact, that
|
||
transcends my scale. If I do not draw a negation from it, at least I
|
||
do not want to found anything on the incomprehensible. I want to
|
||
know whether I can live with what I know and with that alone. I
|
||
am told again that here the intelligence must sacrifice its pride and
|
||
the reason bow down. But if I recognize the limits of the reason, I
|
||
do not therefore negate it, recognizing its relative powers. I merely
|
||
want to remain in this middle path where the intelligence can
|
||
remain clear. If that is its pride, I see no sufficient reason for
|
||
giving it up. Nothing more profound, for example, than
|
||
Kierkegaard’s view according to which despair is not a fact but a
|
||
state: the very state of sin. For sin is what alienates from God. The
|
||
absurd, which is the metaphysical state of the conscious man, does
|
||
not lead to God.[7] Perhaps this notion will become clearer if I risk
|
||
this shocking statement: the absurd is sin without God.
|
||
It is a matter of living in that state of the absurd I know on
|
||
what it is founded, this mind and this world straining against each
|
||
other without being able to embrace each other. I ask for the rule—
|
||
of life of that state, and what I am offered neglects its basis,
|
||
negates one of the terms of the painful opposition, demands of me
|
||
a resignation. I ask what is involved in the condition I recognize as
|
||
mine; I know it implies obscurity and ignorance; and I am assured
|
||
that this ignorance explains everything and that this darkness is my
|
||
light. But there is no reply here to my intent, and this stirring
|
||
lyricism cannot hide the paradox from me. One must therefore turn
|
||
away. Kierkegaard may shout in warning: “If man had no eternal
|
||
consciousness, if, at the bottom of everything, there were merely a
|
||
wild, seething force producing everything, both large and trifling,
|
||
in the storm of dark passions, if the bottomless void that nothing
|
||
can fill underlay all things, what would life be but despair?” This
|
||
cry is not likely to stop the absurd man. Seeking what is true is not
|
||
seeking what is desirable. If in order to elude the anxious question:
|
||
“What would life be?” one must, like the donkey, feed on the roses
|
||
of illusion, then the absurd mind, rather than resigning itself to
|
||
falsehood, prefers, to adopt fearlessly Kierkegaard’s reply:
|
||
“despair.” Everything considered, a determined soul will always
|
||
manage.
|
||
***
|
||
I am taking the liberty at this point of calling the existential
|
||
attitude philosophical suicide. But this does not imply a judgment.
|
||
It is a convenient way of indicating the movement by which a
|
||
thought negates itself and tends to transcend itself in its very
|
||
negation. For the existentials negation is their God. To be precise,
|
||
that god is maintained only through the negation of human
|
||
reason.[8] But, like suicides, gods change with men. There are
|
||
many ways of leaping, the essential being to leap. Those
|
||
redeeming negations, those ultimate contradictions which negate
|
||
the obstacle that has not yet been leaped over, may spring just as
|
||
well (this is the paradox at which this reasoning aims) from a
|
||
certain religious inspiration as from the rational order. They always
|
||
lay claim to the eternal, and it is solely in this that they take the
|
||
leap.
|
||
It must be repeated that the reasoning developed in this essay
|
||
leaves out altogether the most widespread spiritual attitude of our
|
||
enlightened age: the one, based on the principle that all is reason,
|
||
which aims to explain the world. It is natural to give a clear view
|
||
of the world after accepting the idea that it must be clear. That is
|
||
even legitimate, but does not concern the reasoning we are
|
||
following out here. In fact, our aim is to shed light upon the step
|
||
taken by the mind when, starting from a philosophy of the world’s
|
||
lack of meaning, it ends up by finding a meaning and depth in it.
|
||
The most touching of those steps is religious in essence; it
|
||
becomes obvious in the theme of the irrational. But the most
|
||
paradoxical and most significant is certainly the one that attributes
|
||
rational reasons to a world it originally imagined as devoid of any
|
||
guiding principle. It is impossible in any case to reach the
|
||
consequences that concern us without having given an idea of this
|
||
new attainment of the spirit of nostalgia.
|
||
I shall examine merely the theme of “the Intention” made
|
||
fashionable by Husserl and the phenomenologists. I have already
|
||
alluded to it. Originally Husserl’s method negates the classic
|
||
procedure of the reason. Let me repeat. Thinking is not unifying or
|
||
making the appearance familiar under the guise of a great
|
||
principle. Thinking is learning all over again how to see, directing
|
||
one’s consciousness, making of every image a privileged place. In
|
||
other words, phenomenology declines to explain the world, it
|
||
wants to be merely a description of actual experience. It confirms
|
||
absurd thought in its initial assertion that there is no truth, but
|
||
merely truths. From the evening breeze to this hand on my
|
||
shoulder, everything has its truth. Consciousness illuminates it by
|
||
paying attention to it. Consciousness does not form the object of its
|
||
understanding, it merely focuses, it is the act of attention, and, to
|
||
borrow a Bergsonian image, it resembles the projector that
|
||
suddenly focuses on an image. The difference is that there is no
|
||
scenario, but a successive and incoherent illustration. In that magic
|
||
lantern all the pictures are privileged. Consciousness suspends in
|
||
experience the objects of its attention. Through its miracle it
|
||
isolates them. Henceforth they are beyond all judgments. This is
|
||
the “intention” that characterizes consciousness. But the word does
|
||
not imply any idea of finality; it is taken in its sense of “direction”:
|
||
its only value is topographical.
|
||
At first sight, it certainly seems that in this way nothing
|
||
contradicts the absurd spirit. That apparent modesty of thought that
|
||
limits itself to describing what it declines to explain, that
|
||
intentional discipline whence results paradoxically a profound
|
||
enrichment of experience and the rebirth of the world in its
|
||
prolixity are absurd procedures. At least at first sight. For methods
|
||
of thought, in this case as elsewhere, always assume two aspects,
|
||
one psychological and the other metaphysical.[9] Thereby they
|
||
harbor two truths. If the theme of the intentional claims to illustrate
|
||
merely a psychological attitude, by which reality is drained instead
|
||
of being explained, nothing in fact separates it from the absurd
|
||
spirit. It aims to enumerate what it cannot transcend. It affirms
|
||
solely that without any unifying principle thought can still take
|
||
delight in describing and understanding every aspect of experience.
|
||
The truth involved then for each of those aspects is psychological
|
||
in nature. It simply testifies to the “interest” that reality can offer.
|
||
It is a way of awaking a sleeping world and of making it vivid to
|
||
the mind. But if one attempts to extend and give a rational basis to
|
||
that notion of truth, if one claims to discover in this way the
|
||
“essence” of each object of knowledge, one restores its depth to
|
||
experience. For an absurd mind that is incomprehensible. Now, it
|
||
is this wavering between modesty and assurance that is noticeable
|
||
in the intentional attitude, and this shimmering of
|
||
phenomenological thought will illustrate the absurd reasoning
|
||
better than anything else.
|
||
For Husserl speaks likewise of “extra-temporal essences”
|
||
brought to light by the intention, and he sounds like Plato. All
|
||
things are not explained by one thing but by all things. I see no
|
||
difference. To be sure, those ideas or those essences that
|
||
consciousness “effectuates” at the end of every description are not
|
||
yet to be considered perfect models. But it is asserted that they are
|
||
directly present in each datum of perception. There is no longer a
|
||
single idea explaining everything, but an infinite number of
|
||
essences giving a meaning to an infinite number of objects. The
|
||
world comes to a stop, but also lights up. Platonic realism becomes
|
||
intuitive, but it is still realism. Kierkegaard was swallowed up in
|
||
his God; Parmenides plunged thought into the One. But here
|
||
thought hurls itself into an abstract polytheism. But this is not all:
|
||
hallucinations and fictions likewise belong to “extra-temporal
|
||
essences.” In the new world of ideas, the species of centaurs
|
||
collaborates with the more modest species of metropolitan man.
|
||
For the absurd man, there was a truth as well as a bitterness in
|
||
that purely psychological opinion that all aspects of the world are
|
||
privileged. To say that everything is privileged is tantamount to
|
||
saying that everything is equivalent. But the metaphysical aspect of
|
||
that truth is so far-reaching that through an elementary reaction he
|
||
feels closer perhaps to Plato. He is taught, in fact, that every image
|
||
presupposes an equally privileged essence. In this ideal world
|
||
without hierarchy, the formal army is composed solely of generals.
|
||
To be sure, transcendency had been eliminated. But a sudden shift
|
||
in thought brings back into the world a sort of fragmentary
|
||
immanence which restores to the universe its depth.
|
||
Am I to fear having carried too far a theme handled with
|
||
greater circumspection by its creators? I read merely these
|
||
assertions of Husserl, apparently paradoxical yet rigorously logical
|
||
if what precedes is accepted: “That which is true is true absolutely,
|
||
in itself; truth is one, identical with itself, however different the
|
||
creatures who perceive it, men, monsters, angels or gods.” Reason
|
||
triumphs and trumpets forth with that voice, I cannot deny. What
|
||
can its assertions mean in the absurd world? The perception of an
|
||
angel or a god has no meaning for me. That geometrical spot
|
||
where divine reason ratifies mine will always be incomprehensible
|
||
to me. There, too, I discern a leap, and though performed in the
|
||
abstract, it nonetheless means for me forgetting just what I do not
|
||
want to forget. When farther on Husserl exclaims: “If all masses
|
||
subject to attraction were to disappear, the law of attraction would
|
||
not be destroyed but would simply remain without any possible
|
||
application,” I know that I am faced with a metaphysic of
|
||
consolation. And if I want to discover the point where thought
|
||
leaves the path of evidence, I have only to reread the parallel
|
||
reasoning that Husserl voices regarding the mind: “If we could
|
||
contemplate clearly the exact laws of psychic processes, they
|
||
would be seen to be likewise eternal and invariable, like the basic
|
||
laws of theoretical natural science. Hence they would be valid even
|
||
if there were no psychic process.” Even if the mind were not, its
|
||
laws would be! I see then that of a psychological truth Husserl
|
||
aims to make a rational rule: after having denied the integrating
|
||
power of human reason, he leaps by this expedient to eternal
|
||
Reason.
|
||
Husserl’s theme of the “concrete universe” cannot then surprise
|
||
me. If I am told that all essences are not formal but that some are
|
||
material, that the first are the object of logic and the second of
|
||
science, this is merely a question of definition. The abstract, I am
|
||
told, indicates but a part, without consistency in itself, of a
|
||
concrete universal. But the wavering already noted allows me to
|
||
throw light on the confusion of these terms. For that may mean that
|
||
the concrete object of my attention, this sky, the reflection of that
|
||
water on this coat, alone preserve the prestige of the real that my
|
||
interest isolates in the world. And I shall not deny it. But that may
|
||
mean also that this coat itself is universal, has its particular and
|
||
sufficient essence, belongs to the world of forms. I then realize that
|
||
merely the order of the procession has been changed. This world
|
||
has ceased to have its reflection in a higher universe, but the
|
||
heaven of forms is figured in the host of images of this earth. This
|
||
changes nothing for me. Rather than encountering here a taste for
|
||
the concrete, the meaning of the human condition, I find an
|
||
intellectualism sufficiently unbridled to generalize the concrete
|
||
itself.
|
||
* * *
|
||
It is futile to be amazed by the apparent paradox that leads
|
||
thought to its own negation by the opposite paths of humiliated
|
||
reason and triumphal reason. From the abstract god of Husserl to
|
||
the dazzling god of Kierkegaard the distance is not so great.
|
||
Reason and the irrational lead to the same preaching. In truth the
|
||
way matters but little; the will to arrive suffices. The abstract
|
||
philosopher and the religious philosopher start out from the same
|
||
disorder and support each other in the same anxiety. But the
|
||
essential is to explain. Nostalgia is stronger here than knowledge.
|
||
It is significant that the thought of the epoch is at once one of the
|
||
most deeply imbued with a philosophy of the non-significance of
|
||
the world and one of the most divided in its conclusions. It is
|
||
constantly oscillating between extreme rationalization of reality
|
||
which tends to break up that thought into standard reasons and its
|
||
extreme irrationalization which tends to deify it. But this divorce is
|
||
only apparent. It is a matter of reconciliation, and, in both cases,
|
||
the leap suffices. It is always wrongly thought that the notion of
|
||
reason is a oneway notion. To tell the truth, however rigorous it
|
||
may be in its ambition, this concept is nonetheless just as unstable
|
||
as others. Reason bears a quite human aspect, but it also is able to
|
||
turn toward the divine. Since Plotinus, who was the first to
|
||
reconcile it with the eternal climate, it has learned to turn away
|
||
from the most cherished of its principles, which is contradiction, in
|
||
order to integrate into it the strangest, the quite magic one of
|
||
participation.[10] It is an instrument of thought and not thought
|
||
itself. Above all, a man’s thought is his nostalgia.
|
||
Just as reason was able to soothe the melancholy of Plotinus, it
|
||
provides modern anguish the means of calming itself in the
|
||
familiar setting of the eternal. The absurd mind has less luck. For it
|
||
the world is neither so rational nor so irrational. It is unreasonable
|
||
and only that. With Husserl the reason eventually has no limits at
|
||
all. The absurd, on the contrary, establishes its lim-its since it is
|
||
powerless to calm its anguish. Kierkegaard independently asserts
|
||
that a single limit is enough to negate that anguish. But the absurd
|
||
does not go so far. For it that limit is directed solely at the reason’s
|
||
ambitions. The theme of the irrational, as it is conceived by the
|
||
existentials, is reason becoming confused and escaping by negating
|
||
itself. The absurd is lucid reason noting its limits.
|
||
Only at the end of this difficult path does the absurd man
|
||
recognize his true motives. Upon comparing his inner exigence and
|
||
what is then offered him, he suddenly feels he is going to turn
|
||
away. In the universe of Husserl the world becomes clear and that
|
||
longing for familiarity that man’s heart harbors becomes useless.
|
||
In Kierkegaard’s apocalypse that desire for clarity must be given
|
||
up if it wants to be satisfied. Sin is not so much knowing (if it
|
||
were, everybody would be innocent) as wanting to know. Indeed, it
|
||
is the only sin of which the absurd man can feel that it constitutes
|
||
both his guilt and his innocence. He is offered a solution in which
|
||
all the past contradictions have become merely polemical games.
|
||
But this is not the way he experienced them. Their truth must be
|
||
preserved, which consists in not being satisfied. He does not want
|
||
preaching.
|
||
My reasoning wants to be faithful to the evidence that aroused
|
||
it. That evidence is the absurd. It is that divorce between the mind
|
||
that desires and the world that disappoints, my nostalgia for unity,
|
||
this fragmented universe and the contradiction that binds them
|
||
together. Kierkegaard suppresses my nostalgia and Husserl gathers
|
||
together that universe. That is not what I was expecting. It was a
|
||
matter of living and thinking with those dislocations, of knowing
|
||
whether one had to accept or refuse. There can be no question of
|
||
masking the evidence, of suppressing the absurd by denying one of
|
||
the terms of its equation. It is essential to know whether one can
|
||
live with it or whether, on the other hand, logic commands one to
|
||
die of it. I am not interested in philosophical suicide, but rather in
|
||
plain suicide. I merely wish to purge it of its emotional content and
|
||
know its logic and its integrity. Any other position implies for the
|
||
absurd mind deceit and the mind’s retreat before what the mind
|
||
itself has brought to light. Husserl claims to obey the desire to
|
||
escape “the inveterate habit of living and thinking in certain well-
|
||
known and convenient conditions of existence,” but the final leap
|
||
restores in him the eternal and its comfort. The leap does not
|
||
represent an extreme danger as Kierkegaard would like it to do.
|
||
The danger, on the contrary, lies in the subtle instant that precedes
|
||
the leap. Being able to remain on that dizzying crest—that is
|
||
integrity and the rest is subterfuge. I know also that never has
|
||
helplessness inspired such striking harmonies as those of
|
||
Kierkegaard. But if helplessness has its place in the indifferent
|
||
landscapes of history, it has none in a reasoning whose exigence is
|
||
now known.
|
||
Absurd Freedom
|
||
Now the main thing is done, I hold certain facts from which I
|
||
cannot separate. What I know, what is certain, what I cannot deny,
|
||
what I cannot reject—this is what counts. I can negate everything
|
||
of that part of me that lives on vague nostalgias, except this desire
|
||
for unity, this longing to solve, this need for clarity and cohesion. I
|
||
can refute everything in this world surrounding me that offends or
|
||
enraptures me, except this chaos, this sovereign chance and this
|
||
divine equivalence which springs from anarchy. I don’t know
|
||
whether this world has a meaning that transcends it. But I know
|
||
that I do not know that meaning and that it is impossible for me
|
||
just now to know it. What can a meaning outside my condition
|
||
mean to me? I can understand only in human terms. What I touch,
|
||
what resists me—that is what I understand. And these two
|
||
certainties—my appetite for the absolute and for unity and the
|
||
impossibility of reducing this world to a rational and reasonable
|
||
principle—I also know that I cannot reconcile them. What other
|
||
truth can I admit without lying, without bringing in a hope I lack
|
||
and which means nothing within the limits of my condition?
|
||
If I were a tree among trees, a cat among animals, this life
|
||
would have a meaning, or rather this problem would not arise, for I
|
||
should belong to this world. I should be this world to which I am
|
||
now opposed by my whole consciousness and my whole insistence
|
||
upon familiarity. This ridiculous reason is what sets me in
|
||
opposition to all creation. I cannot cross it out with a stroke of the
|
||
pen. What I believe to be true I must therefore preserve. What
|
||
seems to me so obvious, even against me, I must support. And
|
||
what constitutes the basis of that conflict, of that break between the
|
||
world and my mind, but the awareness of it? If therefore I want to
|
||
preserve it, I can through a constant awareness, ever revived, ever
|
||
alert. This is what, for the moment, I must remember. At this
|
||
moment the absurd, so obvious and yet so hard to win, returns to a
|
||
man’s life and finds its home there. At this moment, too, the mind
|
||
can leave the arid, dried-up path of lucid effort. That path now
|
||
emerges in daily life. It encounters the world of the anonymous
|
||
impersonal pronoun “one,” but henceforth man enters in with his
|
||
revolt and his lucidity. He has forgotten how to hope. This hell of
|
||
the present is his Kingdom at last. All problems recover their sharp
|
||
edge. Abstract evidence retreats before the poetry of forms and
|
||
colors. Spiritual conflicts become embodied and return to the
|
||
abject and magnificent shelter of man’s heart. None of them is
|
||
settled. But all are transfigured. Is one going to die, escape by the
|
||
leap, rebuild a mansion of ideas and forms to one’s own scale? Is
|
||
one, on the contrary, going to take up the heart-rending and
|
||
marvelous wager of the absurd? Let’s make a final effort in this
|
||
regard and draw all our conclusions. The body, affection, creation,
|
||
action, human nobility will then resume their places in this mad
|
||
world. At last man will again find there the wine of the absurd and
|
||
the bread of indifference on which he feeds his greatness.
|
||
Let us insist again on the method: it is a matter of persisting. At
|
||
a certain point on his path the absurd man is tempted. History is
|
||
not lacking in either religions or prophets, even without gods. He is
|
||
asked to leap. All he can reply is that he doesn’t fully understand,
|
||
that it is not obvious. Indeed, he does not want to do anything but
|
||
what he fully understands. He is assured that this is the sin of
|
||
pride, but he does not understand the notion of sin; that perhaps
|
||
hell is in store, but he has not enough imagination to visualize that
|
||
strange future; that he is losing immortal life, but that seems to him
|
||
an idle consideration. An attempt is made to get him to admit his
|
||
guilt. He feels innocent. To tell the truth, that is all he feels—his
|
||
irreparable innocence. This is what allows him everything. Hence,
|
||
what he demands of himself is to live solely with what he knows,
|
||
to accommodate himself to what is, and to bring in nothing that is
|
||
not certain. He is told that nothing is. But this at least is a certainty.
|
||
And it is with this that he is concerned: he wants to find out if it is
|
||
possible to live without appeal.
|
||
Now I can broach the notion of suicide. It has already been felt
|
||
what solution might be given. At this point the problem is
|
||
reversed. It was previously a question of finding out whether or not
|
||
life had to have a meaning to be lived. It now becomes clear, on
|
||
the contrary, that it will be lived all the better if it has no meaning.
|
||
Living an experience, a particular fate, is accepting it fully. Now,
|
||
no one will live this fate, knowing it to be absurd, unless he does
|
||
everything to keep before him that absurd brought to light by
|
||
consciousness. Negating one of the terms of the opposition on
|
||
which he lives amounts to escaping it. To abolish conscious revolt
|
||
is to elude the problem. The theme of permanent revolution is thus
|
||
carried into individual experience. Living is keeping the absurd
|
||
alive. Keeping it alive is, above all, contemplating it. Unlike
|
||
Eurydice, the absurd dies only when we turn away from it. One of
|
||
the only coherent philosophical positions is thus revolt. It is a
|
||
constant confrontation between man and his own obscurity. It is an
|
||
insistence upon an impossible transparency. It challenges the world
|
||
anew every second. Just as danger provided man the unique
|
||
opportunity of seizing awareness, so metaphysical revolt extends
|
||
awareness to the whole of experience. It is that constant presence
|
||
of man in his own eyes. It is not aspiration, for it is devoid of hope.
|
||
That revolt is the certainly of a crushing fate, without the
|
||
resignation that ought to accompany it.
|
||
This is where it is seen to what a degree absurd experience is
|
||
remote from suicide. It may be thought that suicide follows
|
||
revolt—but wrongly. For it does not represent the logical outcome
|
||
of revolt. It is just the contrary by the consent it presupposes.
|
||
Suicide, like the leap, is acceptance at its extreme. Everything is
|
||
over and man returns to his essential history. His future, his unique
|
||
and dreadful future—he sees and rushes toward it. In its way,
|
||
suicide settles the absurd. It engulfs the absurd in the same death.
|
||
But I know that in order to keep alive, the absurd cannot be settled.
|
||
It escapes suicide to the extent that it is simultaneously awareness
|
||
and rejection of death. It is, at the extreme limit of the condemned
|
||
man’s last thought, that shoelace that despite everything he sees a
|
||
few yards away, on the very brink of his dizzying fall. The
|
||
contrary of suicide, in fact, is the man condemned to death.
|
||
That revolt gives life its value. Spread out over the whole
|
||
length of a life, it restores its majesty to that life. To a man devoid
|
||
of blinders, there is no finer sight than that of the intelligence at
|
||
grips with a reality that transcends it. The sight of human pride is
|
||
unequaled. No disparagement is of any use. That discipline that the
|
||
mind imposes on itself, that will conjured up out of nothing, that
|
||
face-to-face struggle have something exceptional about them. To
|
||
impoverish that reality whose inhumanity constitutes man’s
|
||
majesty is tantamount to impoverishing him himself. I understand
|
||
then why the doctrines that explain everything to me also debilitate
|
||
me at the same time. They relieve me of the weight of my own life,
|
||
and yet I must carry it alone. At this juncture, I cannot conceive
|
||
that a skeptical metaphysics can be joined to an ethics of
|
||
renunciation.
|
||
Consciousness and revolt, these rejections are the contrary of
|
||
renunciation. Everything that is indomitable and passionate in a
|
||
human heart quickens them, on the contrary, with its own life. It is
|
||
essential to die unrecon-ciled and not of one’s own free will.
|
||
Suicide is a repudi—ation. The absurd man can only drain
|
||
everything to the bitter end, and deplete himself. The absurd is his
|
||
extreme tension, which he maintains constantly by solitary effort,
|
||
for he knows that in that consciousness and in that day-to-day
|
||
revolt he gives proof of his only truth, which is defiance. This is a
|
||
first consequence.
|
||
***
|
||
If I remain in that prearranged position which consists in
|
||
drawing all the conclusions (and nothing else) involved in a newly
|
||
discovered notion, I am faced with a second paradox. In order to
|
||
remain faithful to that method, I have nothing to do with the
|
||
problem of metaphysical liberty. Knowing whether or not man is
|
||
free doesn’t interest me. I can experience only my own freedom.
|
||
As to it, I can have no general notions, but merely a few clear
|
||
insights. The problem of “freedom as such” has no meaning, for it
|
||
is linked in quite a different way with the problem of God.
|
||
Knowing whether or not man is free involves knowing whether he
|
||
can have a master. The absurdity peculiar to this problem comes
|
||
from the fact that the very notion that makes the problem of
|
||
freedom possible also takes away all its meaning. For in the
|
||
presence of God there is less a problem of freedom than a problem
|
||
of evil. You know the alternative: either we are not free and God
|
||
the all-powerful is responsible for evil. Or we are free and
|
||
responsible but God is not all powerful. All the scholastic
|
||
subtleties have neither added anything to nor subtracted anything
|
||
from the acuteness of this paradox.
|
||
This is why I cannot act lost in the glorification or the mere
|
||
definition of a notion which eludes me and loses its meaning as
|
||
soon as it goes beyond the frame of reference of my individual
|
||
experience. I cannot understand what kind of freedom would be
|
||
given me by a higher being. I have lost the sense of hierarchy. The
|
||
only conception of freedom I can have is that of the prisoner or the
|
||
individual in the midst of the State. The only one I know is
|
||
freedom of thought and action. Now if the absurd cancels all my
|
||
chances of eternal freedom, it restores and magnifies, on the other
|
||
hand, my freedom of action. That privation of hope and future
|
||
means an increase in man’s availability.
|
||
Before encountering the absurd, the everyday man lives with
|
||
aims, a concern for the future or for justification (with regard to
|
||
whom or what is not the question). He weighs his chances, he
|
||
counts on “someday,” his retirement or the labor of his sons. He
|
||
still thinks that something in his life can be directed. In truth, he
|
||
acts as if he were free, even if all the facts make a point of
|
||
contradicting that liberty. But after the absurd, everything is upset.
|
||
That idea that “I am,” my way of acting as if everything has a
|
||
meaning (even if, on occasion, I said that nothing has)—all that is
|
||
given the lie in vertiginous fashion by the absurdity of a possible
|
||
death. Thinking of the future, establishing aims for oneself, having
|
||
preferences—all this presupposes a belief in freedom, even if one
|
||
occasionally ascertains that one doesn’t feel it. But at that moment
|
||
I am well aware that that higher liberty, that freedom to be, which
|
||
alone can serve as basis for a truth, does not exist. Death is there as
|
||
the only reality. After death the chips are down. I am not even free,
|
||
either, to perpetuate myself, but a slave, and, above all, a slave
|
||
without hope of an eternal revolution, without recourse to
|
||
contempt. And who without revolution and without contempt can
|
||
remain a slave? What freedom can exist in the fullest sense without
|
||
assurance of eternity?
|
||
But at the same time the absurd man realizes that hitherto he
|
||
was bound to that postulate of freedom on the illusion of which he
|
||
was living. In a certain sense, that hampered him. To the extent to
|
||
which he imagined a purpose to his life, he adapted himself to the
|
||
demands of a purpose to be achieved and became the slave of his
|
||
liberty. Thus I could not act otherwise than as the father (or the
|
||
engineer or the leader of a nation, or the post-office sub-clerk) that
|
||
I am preparing to be. I think I can choose to be that rather than
|
||
something else. I think so unconsciously, to be sure. But at the
|
||
same time I strengthen my postulate with the beliefs of those
|
||
around me, with the presumptions of my human environment
|
||
(others are so sure of being free, and that cheerful mood is so
|
||
contagious!). However far one may remain from any presumption,
|
||
moral or social, one is partly influenced by them and even, for the
|
||
best among them (there are good and bad presumptions), one
|
||
adapts one’s life to them. Thus the absurd man realizes that he was
|
||
not really free. To speak clearly, to the extent to which I hope, to
|
||
which I worry about a truth that might be individual to me, about a
|
||
way of being or creating, to the extent to which I arrange my life
|
||
and prove thereby that I accept its having a meaning, I create for
|
||
myself barriers between which I confine my life. I do like so many
|
||
bureaucrats of the mind and heart who only fill me with disgust
|
||
and whose only vice, I now see clearly, is to take man’s freedom
|
||
seriously.
|
||
The absurd enlightens me on this point: there is no future.
|
||
Henceforth this is the reason for my inner freedom. I shall use two
|
||
comparisons here. Mystics, to begin with, find freedom in giving
|
||
themselves. By losing themselves in their god, by accepting his
|
||
rules, they become secretly free. In spontaneously accepted slavery
|
||
they recover a deeper independence. But what does that freedom
|
||
mean? It may be said, above all, that they feel free with regard to
|
||
themselves, and not so much free as liberated. Likewise,
|
||
completely turned toward death (taken here as the most obvious
|
||
absurdity), the absurd man feels released from everything outside
|
||
that passionate attention crystallizing in him. He enjoys a freedom
|
||
with regard to common rules. It can be seen at this point that the
|
||
initial themes of existential philosophy keep their entire value. The
|
||
return to consciousness, the escape from everyday sleep represent
|
||
the first steps of absurd freedom. But it is existential preaching that
|
||
is alluded to, and with it that spiritual leap which basically escapes
|
||
consciousness. In the same way (this is my second comparison) the
|
||
slaves of antiquity did not belong to themselves. But they knew
|
||
that freedom which consists in not feeling responsible.[11] Death,
|
||
too, has patrician hands which, while crushing, also liberate.
|
||
Losing oneself in that bottomless certainty, feeling henceforth
|
||
sufficiently remote from one’s own life to increase it and take a
|
||
broad view of it—this involves the principle of a liberation. Such
|
||
new independence has a definite time limit, like any freedom of
|
||
action. It does not write a check on eternity. But it takes the place
|
||
of the illusions of freedom, which all stopped with death. The
|
||
divine availability of the condemned man before whom the prison
|
||
doors open in a certain early dawn, that unbelievable
|
||
disinterestedness with regard to everything except for the pure
|
||
flame of life—it is clear that death and the absurd are here the
|
||
principles of the only reasonable freedom: that which a human
|
||
heart can experience and live. This is a second consequence. The
|
||
absurd man thus catches sight of a burning and frigid, transparent
|
||
and limited universe in which nothing is possible but everything is
|
||
given, and beyond which all is collapse and nothingness. He can
|
||
then decide to accept such a universe and draw from it his strength,
|
||
his refusal to hope, and the unyielding evidence of a life without
|
||
consolation.
|
||
***
|
||
But what does life mean in such a universe? Nothing else for
|
||
the moment but indifference to the future and a desire to use up
|
||
everything that is given. Belief in the meaning of life always
|
||
implies a scale of values, a choice, our preferences. Belief in the
|
||
absurd, according to our definitions, teaches the contrary. But this
|
||
is worth examining.
|
||
Knowing whether or not one can live without appeal is all that
|
||
interests me. I do not want to get out of my depth. This aspect of
|
||
life being given me, can I adapt myself to it? Now, faced with this
|
||
particular concern, belief in the absurd is tantamount to
|
||
substituting the quantity of experiences for the quality. If I
|
||
convince myself that this life has no other aspect than that of the
|
||
absurd, if I feel that its whole equilibrium depends on that
|
||
perpetual opposition between my conscious revolt and the darkness
|
||
in which it struggles, if I admit that my freedom has no meaning
|
||
except in relation to its limited fate, then I must say that what
|
||
counts is not the best living but the most living. It is not up to me
|
||
to wonder if this is vulgar or revolting, elegant or deplorable. Once
|
||
and for all, value judgments are discarded here in favor of factual
|
||
judgments. I have merely to draw the conclusions from what I can
|
||
see and to risk nothing that is hypothetical. Supposing that living in
|
||
this way were not honorable, then true propriety would command
|
||
me to be dishonorable.
|
||
The most living; in the broadest sense, that rule means nothing.
|
||
It calls for definition. It seems to begin with the fact that the notion
|
||
of quantity has not been sufficiently explored. For it can account
|
||
for a large share of human experience. A man’s rule of conduct
|
||
and his scale of values have no meaning except through the
|
||
quantity and variety of experiences he has been in a position to
|
||
accumulate. Now, the conditions of modern life impose on the
|
||
majority of men the same quantity of experiences and
|
||
consequently the same profound experience. To be sure, there must
|
||
also be taken into consideration the individual’s spontaneous
|
||
contribution, the “given” element in him. But I cannot judge of
|
||
that, and let me repeat that my rule here is to get along with the
|
||
immediate evidence. I see, then, that the individual character of a
|
||
common code of ethics lies not so much in the ideal importance of
|
||
its basic principles as in the norm of an experience that it is
|
||
possible to measure. To stretch a point somewhat, the Greeks had
|
||
the code of their leisure just as we have the code of our eight-hour
|
||
day. But already many men among the most tragic cause us to
|
||
foresee that a longer experience changes this table of values. They
|
||
make us imagine that adventurer of the everyday who through
|
||
mere quantity of experiences would break all records (I am
|
||
purposely using this sports expression) and would thus win his
|
||
own code of ethics.[12] Yet let’s avoid romanticism and just ask
|
||
ourselves what such an attitude may mean to a man with his mind
|
||
made up to take up his bet and to observe strictly what he takes to
|
||
be the rules of the game.
|
||
Breaking all the records is first and foremost being faced with
|
||
the world as often as possible. How can that be done without
|
||
contradictions and without playing on words? For on the one hand
|
||
the absurd teaches that all experiences are unimportant, and on the
|
||
other it urges toward the greatest quantity of experiences. How,
|
||
then, can one fail to do as so many of those men I was speaking of
|
||
earlier—choose the form of life that brings us the most possible of
|
||
that human matter, thereby introducing a scale of values that on the
|
||
other hand one claims to reject?
|
||
But again it is the absurd and its contradictory life that teaches
|
||
us. For the mistake is thinking that that quantity of experiences
|
||
depends on the circumstances of our life when it depends solely on
|
||
us. Here we have to be over-simple. To two men living the same
|
||
number of years, the world always provides the same sum of
|
||
experiences. It is up to us to be conscious of them. Being aware of
|
||
one’s life, one’s revolt, one’s freedom, and to the maximum, is
|
||
living, and to the maximum. Where lucidity dominates, the scale of
|
||
values becomes useless. Let’s be even more simple. Let us say that
|
||
the sole obstacle, the sole deficiency to be made good, is
|
||
constituted by premature death. Thus it is that no depth, no
|
||
emotion, no passion, and no sacrifice could render equal in the
|
||
eyes of the absurd man (even if he wished it so) a conscious life of
|
||
forty years and a lucidity spread over sixty years.[13] Madness and
|
||
death are his irreparables. Man does not choose. The absurd and
|
||
the extra life it involves therefore do not defend on man’s will, but
|
||
on its contrary, which is death.[14] Weighing words carefully, it is
|
||
altogether a question of luck. One just has to be able to consent to
|
||
this. There will never be any substitute for twenty years of life and
|
||
experience.
|
||
By what is an odd inconsistency in such an alert race, the
|
||
Greeks claimed that those who died young were beloved of the
|
||
gods. And that is true only if you are willing to believe that
|
||
entering the ridiculous world of the gods is forever losing the
|
||
purest of joys, which is feeling, and feeling on this earth. The
|
||
present and the succession of presents before a constantly
|
||
conscious soul is the ideal of the absurd man. But the word “ideal”
|
||
rings false in this connection. It is not even his vocation, but
|
||
merely the third consequence of his reasoning. Having started from
|
||
an anguished awareness of the inhuman, the meditation on the
|
||
absurd returns at the end of its itinerary to the very heart of the
|
||
passionate flames of human revolt.[15]
|
||
* * *
|
||
Thus I draw from the absurd three consequences, which are my
|
||
revolt, my freedom, and my passion. By the mere activity of
|
||
consciousness I transform into a rule of life what was an invitation
|
||
to death—and I refuse suicide. I know, to be sure, the dull
|
||
resonance that vibrates throughout these days. Yet I have but a
|
||
word to say: that it is necessary. When Nietzsche writes: “It clearly
|
||
seems that the chief thing in heaven and on earth is to obey at
|
||
length and in a single direction: in the long run there results
|
||
something for which it is worth the trouble of living on this earth
|
||
as, for example, virtue, art, music, the dance, reason, the mind—
|
||
something that transfigures, something delicate, mad, or divine,”
|
||
he elucidates the rule of a really distinguished code of ethics. But
|
||
he also points the way of the absurd man. Obeying the flame is
|
||
both the easiest and the hardest thing to do. However, it is good for
|
||
man to judge himself occasionally. He is alone in being able to do
|
||
so.
|
||
“Prayer,” says Alain, “is when night descends over thought.”
|
||
“But the mind must meet the night,” reply the mystics and the
|
||
existentials. Yes, indeed, but not that night that is born under
|
||
closed eyelids and through the mere will of man—dark,
|
||
impenetrable night that the mind calls up in order to plunge into it.
|
||
If it must encounter a night, let it be rather that of despair, which
|
||
remains lucid—polar night, vigil of the mind, whence will arise
|
||
perhaps that white and virginal brightness which outlines every
|
||
object in the light of the intelligence. At that degree, equivalence
|
||
encounters passionate understanding. Then it is no longer even a
|
||
question of judging the existential leap. It resumes its place amid
|
||
the age-old fresco of human attitudes. For the spectator, if he is
|
||
conscious, that leap is still absurd. In so far as it thinks it solves the
|
||
paradox, it reinstates it intact. On this score, it is stirring. On this
|
||
score, everything resumes its place and the absurd world is reborn
|
||
in all its splendor and diversity.
|
||
But it is bad to stop, hard to be satisfied with a single way of
|
||
seeing, to go without contradiction, perhaps the most subtle of all
|
||
spiritual forces. The preceding merely defines a way of thinking.
|
||
But the point is to live.
|
||
The Absurd Man
|
||
If Stavrogin believes, he does not think he believes. If he does
|
||
not believe, he does not think he does not believe.
|
||
—The Possessed
|
||
My field,” said Goethe, “is time.” That is indeed the absurd
|
||
speech. What, in fact, is the absurd man? He who, without
|
||
negating it, does nothing for the eternal. Not that nostalgia is
|
||
foreign to him. But he prefers his courage and his reasoning. The
|
||
first teaches him to live without appeal and to get along with what
|
||
he has; the second informs him of his limits. Assured of his
|
||
temporally limited freedom, of his revolt devoid of future, and of
|
||
his mortal consciousness, he lives out his adventure within the
|
||
span of his lifetime. That is his field, that is his action, which he
|
||
shields from any judgment but his own. A greater life cannot mean
|
||
for him another life. That would be unfair. I am not even speaking
|
||
here of that paltry eternity that is called posterity. Mme Roland
|
||
relied on herself. That rashness was taught a lesson. Posterity is
|
||
glad to quote her remark, but forgets to judge it. Mme Roland is
|
||
indifferent to posterity.
|
||
There can be no question of holding forth on ethics. I have seen
|
||
people behave badly with great morality and I note every day that
|
||
integrity has no need of rules. There is but one moral code that the
|
||
absurd man can accept, the one that is not separated from God: the
|
||
one that is dictated. But it so happens that he lives outside that
|
||
God. As for the others (I mean also immoralism), the absurd man
|
||
sees nothing in them but justifications and he has nothing to
|
||
justify. I start out here from the principle of his innocence.
|
||
That innocence is to be feared. “Everything is permitted,”
|
||
exclaims Ivan Karamazov. That, too, smacks of the absurd. But on
|
||
condition that it not be taken in the vulgar sense. I don’t know
|
||
whether or not it has been sufficiently pointed out that it is not an
|
||
outburst of relief or of joy, but rather a bitter acknowledgment of a
|
||
fact. The certainty of a God giving a meaning to life far surpasses
|
||
in attractiveness the ability to behave badly with impunity. The
|
||
choice would not be hard to make. But there is no choice, and that
|
||
is where the bitterness comes in. The absurd does not liberate; it
|
||
binds. It does not authorize all actions. “Everything is permitted”
|
||
does not mean that nothing is forbidden. The absurd merely
|
||
confers an equivalence on the consequences of those actions. It
|
||
does not recommend crime, for this would be childish, but it
|
||
restores to remorse its futility. Likewise, if all experiences are
|
||
indifferent, that of duty is as legitimate as any other. One can be
|
||
virtuous through a whim.
|
||
All systems of morality are based on the idea that an action has
|
||
consequences that legitimize or cancel it. A mind imbued with the
|
||
absurd merely judges that those consequences must be considered
|
||
calmly. It is ready to pay up. In other words, there may be
|
||
responsible persons, but there are no guilty ones, in its opinion. At
|
||
very most, such a mind will consent to use past experience as a
|
||
basis for its future actions. Time will prolong time, and life will
|
||
serve life. In this field that is both limited and bulging with
|
||
possibilities, everything in himself, except his lucidity, seems
|
||
unforeseeable to him. What rule, then, could emanate from that
|
||
unreasonable order? The only truth that might seem instructive to
|
||
him is not formal: it comes to life and unfolds in men. The absurd
|
||
mind cannot so much expect ethical rules at the end of its
|
||
reasoning as, rather, illustrations and the breath of human lives.
|
||
The few following images are of this type. They prolong the
|
||
absurd reasoning by giving it a specific attitude and their warmth.
|
||
Do I need to develop the idea that an example is not necessarily
|
||
an example to be followed (even less so, if possible, in the absurd
|
||
world) and that these illustrations are not therefore models?
|
||
Besides the fact that a certain vocation is required for this, one
|
||
becomes ridiculous, with all due allowance, when drawing from
|
||
Rousseau the conclusion that one must walk on all fours and from
|
||
Nietzsche that one must maltreat one’s mother. “It is essential to be
|
||
absurd,” writes a modern author, “it is not essential to be a dupe.”
|
||
The attitudes of which I shall treat can assume their whole
|
||
meaning only through consideration of their contraries. A sub-
|
||
clerk in the post office is the equal of a conqueror if consciousness
|
||
is common to them. All experiences are indifferent in this regard.
|
||
There are some that do either a service or a disservice to man.
|
||
They do him a service if he is conscious. Otherwise, that has no
|
||
importance: a man’s failures imply judgment, not of
|
||
circumstances, but of himself.
|
||
I am choosing solely men who aim only to expend themselves
|
||
or whom I see to be expending themselves. That has no further
|
||
implications. For the moment I want to speak only of a world in
|
||
which thoughts, like lives, are devoid of future. Everything that
|
||
makes man work and get excited utilizes hope. The sole thought
|
||
that is not mendacious is therefore a sterile thought. In the absurd
|
||
world the value of a notion or of a life is measured by its sterility.
|
||
Don Juanism
|
||
If it were sufficient to love, things would be too easy. The more
|
||
one loves, the stronger the absurd grows. It is not through lack of
|
||
love that Don Juan goes from woman to woman. It is ridiculous to
|
||
represent him as a mystic in quest of total love. But it is indeed
|
||
because he loves them with the same passion and each time with
|
||
his whole self that he must repeat his gift and his profound quest.
|
||
Whence each woman hopes to give him what no one has ever
|
||
given him. Each time they are utterly wrong and merely manage to
|
||
make him feel the need of that repetition. “At last,” exclaims one
|
||
of them, “I have given you love.” Can we be surprised that Don
|
||
Juan laughs at this? “At last? No,” he says, “but once more.” Why
|
||
should it be essential to love rarely in order to love much?
|
||
Is Don Juan melancholy? This is not likely. I shall barely have
|
||
recourse to the legend. That laugh, the conquering insolence, that
|
||
playfulness and love of the theater are all clear and joyous. Every
|
||
healthy creature tends to multiply himself. So it is with Don Juan.
|
||
But, furthermore, melancholy people have two reasons for being
|
||
so: they don’t know or they hope. Don Juan knows and does not
|
||
hope. He reminds one of those artists who know their limits, never
|
||
go beyond them, and in that precarious interval in which they take
|
||
their spiritual stand enjoy all the wonderful ease of masters. And
|
||
that is indeed genius: the intelligence that knows its frontiers. Up
|
||
to the frontier of physical death Don Juan is ignorant of
|
||
melancholy. The moment he knows, his laugh bursts forth and
|
||
makes one forgive everything. He was melancholy at the time
|
||
when he hoped. Today, on the mouth of that woman he recognizes
|
||
the bitter and comforting taste of the only knowledge. Bitter?
|
||
Barely: that necessary imperfection that makes happiness
|
||
perceptible!
|
||
It is quite false to try to see in Don Juan a man brought up on
|
||
Ecclesiastes. For nothing is vanity to him except the hope of
|
||
another life. He proves this because he gambles that other life
|
||
against heaven itself. Longing for desire killed by satisfaction, that
|
||
commonplace of the impotent man, does not belong to him. That is
|
||
all right for Faust, who believed in God enough to sell himself to
|
||
the devil. For Don Juan the thing is simpler. Molina’s Burlador
|
||
ever replies to the threats of hell: “What a long respite you give
|
||
me!” What comes after death is futile, and what a long succession
|
||
of days for whoever knows how to be alive! Faust craved worldly
|
||
goods; the poor man had only to stretch out his hand. It already
|
||
amounted to selling his soul when he was unable to gladden it. As
|
||
for satiety, Don Juan insists upon it, on the contrary. If he leaves a
|
||
woman it is not absolutely because he has ceased to desire her. A
|
||
beautiful woman is always desirable. But he desires another, and
|
||
no, this is not the same thing.
|
||
This life gratifies his every wish, and nothing is worse than
|
||
losing it. This madman is a great wise man. But men who live on
|
||
hope do not thrive in this universe where kindness yields to
|
||
generosity, affection to virile silence, and communion to solitary
|
||
courage. And all hasten to say: “He was a weakling, an idealist or a
|
||
saint.” One has to disparage the greatness that insults.
|
||
* * *
|
||
People are sufficiently annoyed (or that smile of complicity
|
||
that debases what it admires) by Don Juan’s speeches and by that
|
||
same remark that he uses on all women. But to anyone who seeks
|
||
quantity in his joys, the only thing that matters is efficacy. What is
|
||
the use of complicating the passwords that have stood the test? No
|
||
one, neither the woman nor the man, listens to them, but rather to
|
||
the voice that pronounces them. They are the rule, the convention,
|
||
and the courtesy. After they are spoken the most important still
|
||
remains to be done. Don Juan is already getting ready for it. Why
|
||
should he give himself a problem in morality? He is not like
|
||
Milosz’s Manara, who damns himself through a desire to be a
|
||
saint. Hell for him is a thing to be provoked. He has but one reply
|
||
to divine wrath, and that is human honor: “I have honor,” he says
|
||
to the Commander, “and I am keeping my promise because I am a
|
||
knight.” But it would be just as great an error to make an
|
||
immoralist of him. In this regard, he is “like everyone else”: he has
|
||
the moral code of his likes and dislikes. Don Juan can be properly
|
||
understood only by constant reference to what he commonly
|
||
symbolizes: the ordinary seducer and the sexual athlete. He is an
|
||
ordinary seducer.[16] Except for the difference that he is conscious,
|
||
and that is why he is absurd. A seducer who has become lucid will
|
||
not change for all that. Seducing is his condition in life. Only in
|
||
novels does one change condition or become better. Yet it can be
|
||
said that at the same time nothing is changed and everything is
|
||
transformed. What Don Juan realizes in action is an ethic of
|
||
quantity, whereas the saint, on the contrary, tends toward quality.
|
||
Not to believe in the profound meaning of things belongs to the
|
||
absurd man. As for those cordial or wonder-struck faces, he eyes
|
||
them, stores them up, and does not pause over them. Time keeps
|
||
up with him. The absurd man is he who is not apart from time. Don
|
||
Juan does not think of “collecting” women. He exhausts their
|
||
number and with them his chances of life. “Collecting” amounts to
|
||
being capable of living off one’s past. But he rejects regret, that
|
||
other form of hope. He is incapable of looking at portraits.
|
||
* * *
|
||
Is he selfish for all that? In his way, probably. But here, too, it
|
||
is essential to understand one another.
|
||
There are those who are made for living and those who are
|
||
made for loving. At least Don Juan would be inclined to say so.
|
||
But he would do so in a very few words such as he is capable of
|
||
choosing. For the love we are speaking of here is clothed in
|
||
illusions of the eternal. As all the specialists in passion teach us,
|
||
there is no eternal love but what is thwarted. There is scarcely any
|
||
passion without struggle. Such a love culminates only in the
|
||
ultimate contradiction of death. One must be Werther or nothing.
|
||
There, too, there are several ways of committing suicide, one of
|
||
which is the total gift and forget-fulness of self. Don Juan, as well
|
||
as anyone else, knows that this can be stirring. But he is one of the
|
||
very few who know that this is not the important thing. He knows
|
||
just as well that those who turn away from all personal life through
|
||
a great love enrich themselves perhaps but certainly impoverish
|
||
those their love has chosen. A mother or a passionate wife
|
||
necessarily has a closed heart, for it is turned away from the world.
|
||
A single emotion, a single creature, a single face, but all is
|
||
devoured. Quite a different love disturbs Don Juan, and this one is
|
||
liberating. It brings with it all the faces in the world, and its tremor
|
||
comes from the fact that it knows itself to be mortal. Don Juan has
|
||
chosen to be nothing.
|
||
For him it is a matter of seeing clearly. We call love what binds
|
||
us to certain creatures only by reference to a collective way of
|
||
seeing for which books and legends are responsible. But of love I
|
||
know only that mixture of desire, affection, and intelligence that
|
||
binds me to this or that creature. That compound is not the same
|
||
for another person. I do not have the right to cover all these
|
||
experiences with the same name. This exempts one from
|
||
conducting them with the same gestures. The absurd man
|
||
multiplies here again what he cannot unify. Thus he discovers a
|
||
new way of being which liberates him at least as much as it
|
||
liberates those who approach him. There is no noble love but that
|
||
which recognizes itself to be both short-lived and exceptional. All
|
||
those deaths and all those rebirths gathered together as in a sheaf
|
||
make up for Don Juan the flowering of his life. It is his way of
|
||
giving and of vivifying. I let it be decided whether or not one can
|
||
speak of selfishness.
|
||
* * *
|
||
I think at this point of all those who absolutely insist that Don
|
||
Juan be punished. Not only in another life, but even in this one. I
|
||
think of all those tales, legends, and laughs about the aged Don
|
||
Juan. But Don Juan is already ready. To a conscious man old age
|
||
and what it portends are not a surprise. Indeed, he is conscious
|
||
only in so far as he does not conceal its horror from himself. There
|
||
was in Athens a temple dedicated to old age. Children were taken
|
||
there. As for Don Juan, the more people laugh at him, the more his
|
||
figure stands out. Thereby he rejects the one the romantics lent
|
||
him. No one wants to laugh at that tormented, pitiful Don Juan. He
|
||
is pitied; heaven itself will redeem him? But that’s not it. In the
|
||
universe of which Don Juan has a glimpse, ridicule too is included.
|
||
He would consider it normal to be chastised. That is the rule of the
|
||
game. And, indeed, it is typical of his nobility to have accepted all
|
||
the rules of the game. Yet he knows he is right and that there can
|
||
be no question of punishment. A fate is not a punishment.
|
||
That is his crime, and how easy it is to understand why the men
|
||
of God call down punishment on his head. He achieves a
|
||
knowledge without illusions which negates everything they
|
||
profess. Loving and possessing, conquering and consuming—that
|
||
is his way of knowing. (There is significance in that favorite
|
||
Scriptural word that calls the carnal act “knowing.”) He is their
|
||
worst enemy to the extent that he is ignorant of them. A chronicler
|
||
relates that the true Burlador died assassinated by Fransciscans
|
||
who wanted “to put an end to the excesses and blasphemies of Don
|
||
Juan, whose birth assured him impunity.” Then they proclaimed
|
||
that heaven had struck him down. No one has proved that strange
|
||
end. Nor has anyone proved the contrary. But without wondering if
|
||
it is probable, I can say that it is logical. I want merely to single out
|
||
at this point the word “birth” and to play on words: it was the fact
|
||
of living that assured his innocence. It was from death alone that
|
||
he derived a guilt now become legendary.
|
||
What else does that stone Commander signify, that cold statue
|
||
set in motion to punish the blood and courage that dared to think?
|
||
All the powers of eternal Reason, of order, of universal morality,
|
||
all the foreign grandeur of a God open to wrath are summed up in
|
||
him. That gigantic and soulless stone merely symbolizes the forces
|
||
that Don Juan negated forever. But the Commander’s mission
|
||
stops there. The thunder and lightning can return to the imitation
|
||
heaven whence they were called forth. The real tragedy takes place
|
||
quite apart from them. No, it was not under a stone hand that Don
|
||
Juan met his death. I am inclined to believe in the legendary
|
||
bravado, in that mad laughter of the healthy man provoking a non-
|
||
existent God. But, above all, I believe that on that evening when
|
||
Don Juan was waiting at Anna’s the Commander didn’t come, and
|
||
that after midnight the blasphemer must have felt the dreadful
|
||
bitterness of those who have been right. I accept even more readily
|
||
the account of his life that has him eventually burying himself in a
|
||
monastery. Not that the edifying aspect of the story can he
|
||
considered probable. What refuge can he go ask of God? But this
|
||
symbolizes rather the logical outcome of a life completely imbued
|
||
with the absurd, the grim ending of an existence turned toward
|
||
short lived joys. At this point sensual pleasure winds up in
|
||
asceticism. It is essential to realize that they may be, as it were, the
|
||
two aspects of the same destitution. What more ghastly image can
|
||
be called up than that of a man betrayed by his body who, simply
|
||
because he did not die in time, lives out the comedy while awaiting
|
||
the end, face to face with that God he does not adore, serving him
|
||
as he served life, kneeling before a void and arms outstretched
|
||
toward a heaven without eloquence that he knows to he also
|
||
without depth?
|
||
I see Don Juan in a cell of one of those Spanish monasteries
|
||
lost on a hilltop. And if he contemplates anything at all, it is not the
|
||
ghosts of past loves, but perhaps, through a narrow slit in the sun-
|
||
baked wall, some silent Spanish plain, a noble, soulless land in
|
||
which he recognizes himself. Yes, it is on this melancholy and
|
||
radiant image that the curtain must be rung down. The ultimate
|
||
end, awaited but never desired, the ultimate end is negligible.
|
||
Drama
|
||
“The play’s the thing,” says Hamlet, “wherein I’ll catch the
|
||
conscience of the king.”
|
||
“Catch” is indeed the word. For conscience moves swiftly or
|
||
withdraws within itself. It has to be caught on the wing, at that
|
||
barely perceptible moment when it glances fleetingly at itself. The
|
||
everyday man does not enjoy tarrying. Everything, on the contrary,
|
||
hurries him onward. But at the same time nothing interests him
|
||
more than himself, especially his potentialities. Whence his interest
|
||
in the theater, in the show, where so many fates are offered him,
|
||
where he can accept the poetry without feeling the sorrow. There at
|
||
least can be recognized the thoughtless man, and he continues to
|
||
hasten toward some hope or other. The absurd man begins where
|
||
that one leaves off, where, ceasing to admire the play, the mind
|
||
wants to enter in. Entering into all these lives, experiencing them
|
||
in their diversity, amounts to acting them out. I am not saying that
|
||
actors in general obey that impulse, that they are absurd men, but
|
||
that their fate is an absurd fate which might charm and attract a
|
||
lucid heart. It is necessary to establish this in order to grasp
|
||
without misunderstanding what will follow.
|
||
The actor’s realm is that of the fleeting. Of all kinds of fame, it
|
||
is known, his is the most ephemeral. At least, this is said in
|
||
conversation. But all kinds of fame are ephemeral. From the point
|
||
of view of Sirius, Goethe’s works in ten thousand years will be
|
||
dust and his name forgotten. Perhaps a handful of archaeologists
|
||
will look for “evidence” as to our era. That idea has always
|
||
contained a lesson. Seriously meditated upon, it reduces our
|
||
perturbations to the profound nobility that is found in indifference.
|
||
Above all, it directs our concerns toward what is most certain—
|
||
that is, toward the immediate. Of all kinds of fame the least
|
||
deceptive is the one that is lived.
|
||
Hence the actor has chosen multiple fame, the fame that is
|
||
hallowed and tested. From the fact that everything is to die
|
||
someday he draws the best conclusion. An actor succeeds or does
|
||
not succeed. A writer has some hope even if he is not appreciated.
|
||
He assumes that his works will bear witness to what he was. At
|
||
best the actor will leave us a photograph, and nothing of what he
|
||
was himself, his gestures and his silences, his gasping or his
|
||
panting with love, will come down to us. For him, not to be known
|
||
is not to act, and not acting is dying a hundred times with all the
|
||
creatures he would have brought to life or resuscitated.
|
||
***
|
||
Why should we be surprised to find a fleeting fame built upon
|
||
the most ephemeral of creations? The actor has three hours to be
|
||
Iago or Alceste, Phedre or Gloucester. In that short space of time
|
||
he makes them come to life and die on fifty square yards of boards.
|
||
Never has the absurd been so well illustrated or at such length.
|
||
What more revelatory epitome can be imagined than those
|
||
marvelous lives, those exceptional and total desti—
|
||
nies unfolding for a few hours within a stage set? Off the stage,
|
||
Sigismundo ceases to count. Two hours later he is seen dining out.
|
||
Then it is, perhaps, that life is a dream. But after Sigismundo
|
||
comes another. The hero suffering from uncertainty takes the place
|
||
of the man roaring for his revenge. By thus sweeping over
|
||
centuries and minds, by miming man as he can be and as he is, the
|
||
actor has much in common with that other absurd individual, the
|
||
traveler. Like him, he drains something and is constantly on the
|
||
move. He is a traveler in time and, for the best, the hunted traveler,
|
||
pursued by souls. If ever the ethics of quantity could find
|
||
sustenance, it is indeed on that strange stage. To what degree the
|
||
actor benefits from the characters is hard to say. But that is not the
|
||
important thing. It is merely a matter of knowing how far he
|
||
identifies himself with those irreplaceable lives. It often happens
|
||
that he carries them with him, that they somewhat overflow the
|
||
time and place in which they were born. They accompany the
|
||
actor, who cannot very readily separate himself from what he has
|
||
been. Occasionally when reaching for his glass he resumes
|
||
Hamlet’s gesture of raising his cup. No, the distance separating
|
||
him from the creatures into whom he infuses life is not so great. He
|
||
abundantly illustrates every month or every day that so suggestive
|
||
truth that there is no frontier between what a man wants to be and
|
||
what he is. Always concerned with better representing, he
|
||
demonstrates to what a degree appearing creates being. For that is
|
||
his art—to simulate absolutely, to project himself as deeply as
|
||
possible into lives that are not his own. At the end of his effort his
|
||
vocation becomes clear: to apply himself wholeheartedly to being
|
||
nothing or to being several. The narrower the limits allotted him
|
||
for creating his character, the more necessary his talent. He will die
|
||
in three hours under the mask he has assumed today. Within three
|
||
hours he must experience and express a whole exceptional life.
|
||
That is called losing oneself to find oneself. In those three hours he
|
||
travels the whole course of the dead-end path that the man in the
|
||
audience takes a lifetime to cover.
|
||
* * *
|
||
A mime of the ephemeral, the actor trains and perfects himself
|
||
only in appearances. The theatrical convention is that the heart
|
||
expresses itself and communicates itself only through gestures and
|
||
in the body—or through the voice, which is as much of the soul as
|
||
of the body. The rule of that art insists that everything be
|
||
magnified and translated into flesh. If it were essential on the stage
|
||
to love as people really love, to employ that irreplaceable voice of
|
||
the heart, to look as people contemplate in life, our speech would
|
||
be in code. But here silences must make themselves heard. Love
|
||
speaks up louder, and immobility itself becomes spectacular. The
|
||
body is king, Not everyone can be “theatrical,” and this unjustly
|
||
maligned word covers a whole aesthetic and a whole ethic. Half a
|
||
man’s life is spent in implying, in turning away, and in keeping
|
||
silent. Here the actor is the intruder. He breaks the spell chaining
|
||
that soul, and at last the passions can rush onto their stage. They
|
||
speak in every gesture; they live only through shouts and cries.
|
||
Thus the actor creates his characters for display. He outlines or
|
||
sculptures them and slips into their imaginary form, transfusing his
|
||
blood into their phantoms. I am of course speaking of great drama,
|
||
the kind that gives the actor an opportunity to fulfill his wholly
|
||
physical fate. Take Shakespeare, for instance. In that impulsive
|
||
drama the physical passions lead the dance. They explain
|
||
everything. Without them all would collapse. Never would King
|
||
Lear keep the appointment set by madness without the brutal
|
||
gesture that exiles Cordelia and condemns Edgar. It is just that the
|
||
unfolding of that tragedy should thenceforth be dominated by
|
||
madness. Souls are given over to the demons and their saraband.
|
||
No fewer than four madmen: one by trade, another by intention,
|
||
and the last two through suffering—four disordered bodies, four
|
||
unutterable aspects of a single condition.
|
||
The very scale of the human body is inadequate. The mask and
|
||
the buskin, the make-up that reduces and accentuates the face in its
|
||
essential elements, the costume that exaggerates and simplifies—
|
||
that universe sacrifices everything to appearance and is made
|
||
solely for the eye. Through an absurd miracle, it is the body that
|
||
also brings knowledge. I should never really understand Iago
|
||
unless I played his part. It is not enough to hear him, for I grasp
|
||
him only at the moment when I see him. Of the absurd character
|
||
the actor consequently has the monotony, that single, oppressive
|
||
silhouette, simultaneously strange and familiar, that he carries
|
||
about from hero to hero. There, too, the great dramatic work
|
||
contributes to this unity of tone.[17] This is where the actor
|
||
contradicts himself: the same and yet so various, so many souls
|
||
summed up in a single body. Yet it is the absurd contradiction
|
||
itself, that individual who wants to achieve everything and live
|
||
everything, that useless attempt, that ineffectual persistence. What
|
||
always contradicts itself nevertheless joins in him. He is at that
|
||
point where body and mind converge, where the mind, tired of its
|
||
defeats, turns toward its most faithful ally. “And blest are those,”
|
||
says Hamlet, “whose blood and judgment are so well commingled
|
||
that they are not a pipe for fortune’s finger to sound what stop she
|
||
please.”
|
||
How could the Church have failed to condemn such a practice
|
||
on the part of the actor? She repudiated in that art the heretical
|
||
multiplication of souls, the emotional debauch, the scandalous
|
||
presumption of a mind that objects to living but one life and hurls
|
||
itself into all forms of excess. She proscribed in them that
|
||
preference for the present and that triumph of Proteus which are
|
||
the negation of everything she teaches. Eternity is not a game. A
|
||
mind foolish enough to prefer a comedy to eternity has lost its
|
||
salvation. Between “everywhere” and “forever” there is no
|
||
compromise. Whence that much maligned profession can give rise
|
||
to a tremendous spiritual conflict. “What matters,” said Nietzsche,
|
||
“is not eternal life but eternal vivacity.” All drama is, in fact, in
|
||
this choice. Celimene against Elianthe, the whole subject in the
|
||
absurd consequence of a nature carried to its extreme, and the
|
||
verse itself, the “bad verse,” barely accented like the monotony of
|
||
the character’s nature.
|
||
Adrienne Lecouvreur on her deathbed was willing to confess
|
||
and receive communion, but refused to abjure her profession. She
|
||
thereby lost the benefit of the confession. Did this not amount, in
|
||
effect, to choosing her absorbing passion in preference to God?
|
||
And that woman in the death throes refusing in tears to repudiate
|
||
what she called her art gave evidence of a greatness that she never
|
||
achieved behind the footlights. This was her finest role and the
|
||
hardest one to play. Choosing between heaven and a ridiculous
|
||
fidelity, preferring oneself to eternity or losing oneself in God is
|
||
the age-old tragedy in which each must play his part.
|
||
The actors of the era knew they were excommunicated.
|
||
Entering the profession amounted to choosing Hell. And the
|
||
Church discerned in them her worst enemies. A few men of letters
|
||
protest: “What! Refuse the last rites to Moliere!” But that was just,
|
||
and especially in one who died onstage and finished under the
|
||
actor’s make-up a life entirely devoted to dispersion. In his case
|
||
genius is invoked, which excuses everything. But genius excuses
|
||
nothing, just because it refuses to do so.
|
||
The actor knew at that time what punishment was in store for
|
||
him. But what significance could such vague threats have
|
||
compared to the final punishment that life itself was reserving for
|
||
him? This was the one that he felt in advance and accepted wholly.
|
||
To the actor as to the absurd man, a premature death is irreparable.
|
||
Nothing can make up for the sum of faces and centuries he would
|
||
otherwise have traversed. But in any case, one has to die. For the
|
||
actor is doubtless everywhere, but time sweeps him along, too, and
|
||
makes its impression with him.
|
||
It requires but a little imagination to feel what an actor’s fate
|
||
means. It is in time that he makes up and enumerates his
|
||
characters. It is in time likewise that he learns to dominate them.
|
||
The greater number of different lives he has lived, the more aloof
|
||
he can be from them. The time comes when he must die to the
|
||
stage and for the world. What he has lived faces him. He sees
|
||
clearly. He feels the harrowing and irreplaceable quality of that
|
||
adventure. He knows and can now die. There are homes for aged
|
||
actors.
|
||
Conquest
|
||
“No,” says the conqueror, “don’t assume that because I love
|
||
action I have had to forget how to think. On the contrary I can
|
||
throughly define what I believe. For I believe it firmly and I see it
|
||
surely and clearly. Beware of those who say: ‘I know this too well
|
||
to be able to express it.’ For if they cannot do so, this is because
|
||
they don’t know it or because out of laziness they stopped at the
|
||
outer crust.
|
||
“I have not many opinions. At the end of a life man notices that
|
||
he has spent years becoming sure of a single truth. But a single
|
||
truth, if it is obvious, is enough to guide an existence. As for me, I
|
||
decidedly have something to say about the individual. One must
|
||
speak of him bluntly and, if need be, with the appropriate
|
||
contempt.
|
||
“A man is more a man through the things he keeps to himself
|
||
than through those he says. There are many that I shall keep to
|
||
myself. But I firmly believe that all those who have judged the
|
||
individual have done so with much less experience than we on
|
||
which to base their judgment. The intelligence, the stirring
|
||
intelligence perhaps foresaw what it was essential to note. But the
|
||
era, its ruins, and its blood overwhelm us with facts. It was
|
||
possible for ancient nations, and even for more recent ones down
|
||
to our machine age, to weigh one against the other the virtues of
|
||
society and of the individual, to try to find out which was to serve
|
||
the other. To begin with, that was possible by virtue of that
|
||
stubborn aberration in man’s heart according to which human
|
||
beings were created to serve or be served. In the second place, it
|
||
was possible because neither society nor the individual had yet
|
||
revealed all their ability.
|
||
“I have seen bright minds express astonishment at the
|
||
masterpieces of Dutch painters born at the height of the bloody
|
||
wars in Flanders, be amazed by the prayers of Silesian mystics
|
||
brought up during the frightful Thirty Years’ War. Eternal values
|
||
survive secular turmoils before their astonished eyes. But there has
|
||
been progress since. The painters of today are deprived of such
|
||
serenity. Even if they have basically the heart the creator needs—I
|
||
mean the closed heart—it is of no use; for everyone, including the
|
||
saint himself, is mobilized. This is perhaps what I have felt most
|
||
deeply. At every form that miscarries in the trenches, at every
|
||
outline, metaphor, or prayer crushed under steel, the eternal loses a
|
||
round. Conscious that I cannot stand aloof from my time, I have
|
||
decided to be an integral part of it. This is why I esteem the
|
||
individual only because he strikes me as ridiculous and humiliated.
|
||
Knowing that there are no victorious causes, I have a liking for lost
|
||
causes: they require an uncontaminated soul, equal to its defeat as
|
||
to its temporary victories. For anyone who feels bound up with this
|
||
world’s fate, the clash of civilizations has something agonizing
|
||
about it. I have made that anguish mine at the same time that I
|
||
wanted to join in. Between history and the eternal I have chosen
|
||
history because I like certainties. Of it, at least, I am certain, and
|
||
how can I deny this force crushing me?
|
||
“There always comes a time when one must choose between
|
||
contemplation and action. This is called becoming a man. Such
|
||
wrenches are dreadful. But for a proud heart there can be no
|
||
compromise. There is God or time, that cross or this sword. This
|
||
world has a higher meaning that transcends its worries, or nothing
|
||
is true but those worries. One must live with time and die with it,
|
||
or else elude it for a greater life. I know that one can compromise
|
||
and live in the world while believing in the eternal. That is called
|
||
accepting. But I loathe this term and want all or nothing. If I
|
||
choose action, don’t think that contemplation is like an unknown
|
||
country to me. But it cannot give me everything, and, deprived of
|
||
the eternal, I want to ally myself with time. I do not want to put
|
||
down to my account either nostalgia or bitterness, and I merely
|
||
want to see clearly. I tell you, tomorrow you will be mobilized. For
|
||
you and for me that is a liberation. The individual can do nothing
|
||
and yet he can do everything. In that wonderful unattached state
|
||
you understand why I exalt and crush him at one and the same
|
||
time. It is the world that pulverizes him and I who liberate him. I
|
||
provide him with all his rights.
|
||
“Conquerors know that action is in itself useless. There is but
|
||
one useful action, that of remaking man and the earth. I shall never
|
||
remake men. But one must do ’as if.’ For the path of struggle leads
|
||
me to the flesh. Even humiliated, the flesh is my only certainty. I
|
||
can live only on it. The creature is my native land. This is why I
|
||
have chosen this absurd and ineffectual effort. This is why I am on
|
||
the side of the struggle. The epoch lends itself to this, as I have
|
||
said. Hitherto the greatness of a conqueror was geographical. It
|
||
was measured by the extent of the conquered territories. There is a
|
||
reason why the word has changed in meaning and has ceased to
|
||
signify the victorious general. The greatness has changed camp. It
|
||
lies in protest and the blind-alley sacrifice. There, too, it is not
|
||
through a preference for defeat. Victory would be desirable. But
|
||
there is but one victory, and it is eternal. That is the one I shall
|
||
never have. That is where I stumble and cling. A revolution is
|
||
always accomplished against the gods, beginning with the
|
||
revolution of Prometheus, the first of modern conquerors. It is
|
||
man’s demands made against his fate; the demands of the poor are
|
||
but a pretext. Yet I can seize that spirit only in its historical act,
|
||
and that is where I make contact with it. Don’t assume, however,
|
||
that I take pleasure in it: opposite the essential contradiction, I
|
||
maintain my human contradiction. I establish my lucidity in the
|
||
midst of what negates it. I exalt man be-fore what crushes him, and
|
||
my freedom, my revolt, and my passion come together then in that
|
||
tension, that lucidity, and that vast repetition.
|
||
“Yes, man is his own end. And he is his only end. If he aims to
|
||
be something, it is in this life. Now I know it only too well.
|
||
Conquerors sometimes talk of vanquishing and overcoming. But it
|
||
is always ‘overcoming oneself’ that they mean. You are well aware
|
||
of what that means. Every man has felt himself to be the equal of a
|
||
god at certain moments. At least, this is the way it is expressed.
|
||
But this comes from the fact that in a flash he felt the amazing
|
||
grandeur of the human mind. The conquerors are merely those
|
||
among men who are conscious enough of their strength to be sure
|
||
of living constantly on those heights and fully aware of that
|
||
grandeur. It is a question of arithmetic, of more or less. The
|
||
conquerors are capable of the more. But they are capable of no
|
||
more than man himself when he wants. This is why they never
|
||
leave the human crucible, plunging into the seething soul of
|
||
revolutions.
|
||
“There they find the creature mutilated, but they also encounter
|
||
there the only values they like and admire, man and his silence.
|
||
This is both their destitution and their wealth. There is but one
|
||
luxury for them—that of human relations. How can one fail to
|
||
realize that in this vulnerable universe everything that is human
|
||
and solely human assumes a more vivid meaning? Taut faces,
|
||
threatened fraternity, such strong and chaste friendship among
|
||
men—these are the true riches because they are transitory. In their
|
||
midst the mind is most aware of its powers and limitations. That is
|
||
to say, its efficacity. Some have spoken of genius. But genius is
|
||
easy to say; I prefer the intelligence. It must be said that it can be
|
||
magnificent then. It lights up this desert and dominates it. It knows
|
||
its obligations and illustrates them. It will die at the same time as
|
||
this body. But knowing this constitutes its freedom.
|
||
“We are not ignorant of the fact that all churches are against us.
|
||
A heart so keyed up eludes the eternal, and all churches, divine or
|
||
political, lay claim to the eternal. Happiness and courage,
|
||
retribution or justice are secondary ends for them. It is a doctrine
|
||
they bring, and one must subscribe to it. But I have no concern
|
||
with ideas or with the eternal. The truths that come within my
|
||
scope can be touched with the hand. I cannot separate from them.
|
||
This is why you cannot base anything on me: nothing of the
|
||
conqueror lasts, not even his doctrines.
|
||
“At the end of all that, despite everything, is death. We know
|
||
also that it ends everything. This is why those cemeteries all over
|
||
Europe, which obsess some among us, are hideous. People beautify
|
||
only what they love, and death repels us and tires our patience. It,
|
||
too, is to be conquered. The last Carrara, a prisoner in Padua
|
||
emptied by the plague and besieged by the Venetians, ran
|
||
screaming through the halls of his deserted palace: he was calling
|
||
on the devil and asking him for death. This was a way of
|
||
overcoming it. And it is likewise a mark of courage characteristic
|
||
of the Occident to have made so ugly the places where death thinks
|
||
itself honored. In the rebel s universe, death exalts injustice. It is
|
||
the supreme abuse.
|
||
“Others, without compromising either, have chosen the eternal
|
||
and denounced the illusion of this world. Their cemeteries smile
|
||
amid numerous flowers and birds. That suits the conqueror and
|
||
gives him a clear image of what he has rejected. He has chosen, on
|
||
the contrary, the black iron fence or the potter’s field. The best
|
||
among the men of God occasionally are seized with fright mingled
|
||
with consideration and pity for minds that can live with such an
|
||
image of their death. Yet those minds derive their strength and
|
||
justification from this. Our fate stands before us and we provoke
|
||
him. Less out of pride than out of awareness of our ineffectual
|
||
condition. We, too, sometimes feel pity for ourselves. It is the only
|
||
compassion that seems acceptable to us: a feeling that perhaps you
|
||
hardly understand and that seems to you scarcely virile. Yet the
|
||
most daring among us are the ones who feel it. But we call the
|
||
lucid ones virile and we do not want a strength that is apart from
|
||
lucidity.”
|
||
* * *
|
||
Let me repeat that these images do not propose moral codes
|
||
and involve no judgments: they are sketches. They merely
|
||
represent a style of life. The lover, the actor, or the adventurer
|
||
plays the absurd. But equally well, if he wishes, the chaste man,
|
||
the civil servant, or the president of the Republic. It is enough to
|
||
know and to mask nothing. In Italian museums are sometimes
|
||
found little painted screens that the priest used to hold in front of
|
||
the face of condemned men to hide the scaffold from them. The
|
||
leap in all its forms, rushing into the divine or the eternal,
|
||
surrendering to the illusions of the everyday or of the idea—all
|
||
these screens hide the absurd. But there are civil servants without
|
||
screens, and they are the ones of whom I mean to speak. I have
|
||
chosen the most extreme ones. At this level the absurd gives them
|
||
a royal power. It is true that those princes are without a kingdom.
|
||
But they have this advantage over others: they know that all
|
||
royalties are illusory. They know that is their whole nobility, and it
|
||
is useless to speak in relation to them of hidden misfortune or the
|
||
ashes of disillusion. Being deprived of hope is not despairing. The
|
||
flames of earth are surely worth celestial perfumes. Neither I nor
|
||
anyone can judge them here. They are not striving to be better;
|
||
they are attempting to be consistent. If the term “wise man” can be
|
||
applied to the man who lives on what he has without speculating
|
||
on what he has not, then they are wise men. One of them, a
|
||
conqueror but in the realm of mind, a Don Juan but of knowledge,
|
||
an actor but of the intelligence, knows this better than anyone:
|
||
“You nowise deserve a privilege on earth and in heaven for having
|
||
brought to perfection your dear little meek sheep; you nonetheless
|
||
continue to be at best a ridiculous dear little sheep with horns and
|
||
nothing more—even supposing that you do not burst with vanity
|
||
and do not create a scandal by posing as a judge.”
|
||
In any case, it was essential to restore to the absurd reasoning
|
||
more cordial examples. The imagination can add many others,
|
||
inseparable from time and exile, who likewise know how to live in
|
||
harmony with a universe without future and without weakness.
|
||
This absurd, godless world is, then, peopled with men who think
|
||
clearly and have ceased to hope. And I have not yet spoken of the
|
||
most absurd character, who is the creator.
|
||
Absurd Creation
|
||
Philosophy and Fiction
|
||
All those lives maintained in the rarefied air of the absurd
|
||
could not persevere without some profound and constant thought
|
||
to infuse its strength into them. Right here, it can be only a strange
|
||
feeling of fidelity. Conscious men have been seen to fulfill their
|
||
task amid the most stupid of wars without considering themselves
|
||
in contradiction. This is because it was essential to elude nothing.
|
||
There is thus a metaphysical honor in enduring the world’s
|
||
absurdity. Conquest or play-acting, multiple loves, absurd revolt
|
||
are tributes that man pays to his dignity in a campaign in which he
|
||
is defeated in advance.
|
||
It is merely a matter of being faithful to the rule of the battle.
|
||
That thought may suffice to sustain a mind; it has supported and
|
||
still supports whole civilizations. War cannot be negated. One
|
||
must live it or die of it. So it is with the absurd: it is a question of
|
||
breathing with it, of recognizing its lessons and recovering their
|
||
flesh. In this regard the absurd joy par excellence is creation. “Art
|
||
and nothing but art,” said Nietzsche; “we have art in order not to
|
||
die of the truth.”
|
||
In the experience that I am attempting to describe and to stress
|
||
on several modes, it is certain that a new torment arises wherever
|
||
another dies. The childish chasing after forgetfulness, the appeal of
|
||
satisfaction are now devoid of echo. But the constant tension that
|
||
keeps man face to face with the world, the ordered delirium that
|
||
urges him to be receptive to everything leave him another fever. In
|
||
this universe the work of art is then the sole chance of keeping his
|
||
consciousness and of fixing its adventures. Creating is living
|
||
doubly. The groping, anxious quest of a Proust, his meticulous
|
||
collecting of flowers, of wallpapers, and of anxieties, signifies
|
||
nothing else. At the same time, it has no more significance than the
|
||
continual and imperceptible creation in which the actor, the
|
||
conqueror, and all absurd men indulge every day of their lives. All
|
||
try their hands at miming, at repeating, and at recreating the reality
|
||
that is theirs. We always end up by having the appearance of our
|
||
truths. All existence for a man turned away from the eternal is but
|
||
a vast mime under the mask of the absurd. Creation is the great
|
||
mime.
|
||
Such men know to begin with, and then their whole effort is to
|
||
examine, to enlarge, and to enrich the ephemeral island on which
|
||
they have just landed. But first they must know. For the absurd
|
||
discovery coincides with a pause in which future passions are
|
||
prepared and justified. Even men without a gospel have their
|
||
Mount of Olives. And one must not fall asleep on theirs either. For
|
||
the absurd man it is not a matter of explaining and solving, but of
|
||
experiencing and describing. Everything begins with lucid
|
||
indifference.
|
||
Describing—that is the last ambition of an absurd thought.
|
||
Science likewise, having reached the end of its paradoxes, ceases
|
||
to propound and stops to contemplate and sketch the ever virgin
|
||
landscape of phenomena. The heart learns thus that the emotion
|
||
delighting us when we see the world’s aspects comes to us not
|
||
from its depth but from their diversity. Explanation is useless, but
|
||
the sensation remains and, with it, the constant attractions of a
|
||
universe inexhaustible in quantity. The place of the work of art can
|
||
be understood at this point.
|
||
It marks both the death of an experience and its multiplication.
|
||
It is a sort of monotonous and passionate repetition of the themes
|
||
already orchestrated by the world: the body, inexhaustible image
|
||
on the pediment of temples, forms or colors, number or grief. It is
|
||
therefore not indifferent, as a conclusion, to encounter once again
|
||
the principal themes of this essay in the wonderful and childish
|
||
world of the creator. It would be wrong to see a symbol in it and to
|
||
think that the work of art can be considered at last as a refuge for
|
||
the absurd. It is itself an absurd phenomenon, and we are
|
||
concerned merely with its description. It does not offer an escape
|
||
for the intellectual ailment. Rather, it is one of the symptoms of
|
||
that ailment which reflects it throughout a man’s whole thought.
|
||
But for the first time it makes the mind get outside of itself and
|
||
places it in opposition to others, not for it to get lost but to show it
|
||
clearly the blind path that all have entered upon. In the time of the
|
||
absurd reasoning, creation follows indifference and discovery. It
|
||
marks the point from which absurd passions spring and where the
|
||
reasoning stops. Its place in this essay is justified in this way.
|
||
It will suffice to bring to light a few themes common to the
|
||
creator and the thinker in order to find in the work of art all the
|
||
contradictions of thought involved in the absurd. Indeed, it is not
|
||
so much identical conclusions that prove minds to be related as the
|
||
contradictions that are common to them. So it is with thought and
|
||
creation. I hardly need to say that the same anguish urges man to
|
||
these two attitudes. This is where they coincide in the beginning.
|
||
But among all the thoughts that start from the absurd, I have seen
|
||
that very few remain within it. And through their deviations or
|
||
infidelities I have best been able to measure what belonged to the
|
||
absurd. Similarly I must wonder: is an absurd work of art possible?
|
||
* * *
|
||
It would be impossible to insist too much on the arbitrary
|
||
nature of the former opposition between art and philosophy. If you
|
||
insist on taking it in too limited a sense, it is certainly false. If you
|
||
mean merely that these two disciplines each have their peculiar
|
||
climate, that is probably true but remains vague. The only
|
||
acceptable argument used to lie in the contradiction brought up
|
||
between the philosopher enclosed within his system and the artist
|
||
placed before his work. But this was pertinent for a certain form of
|
||
art and of philosophy which we consider secondary here. The idea
|
||
of an art detached from its creator is not only outmoded; it is false.
|
||
In opposition to the artist, it is pointed out that no philosopher ever
|
||
created several systems. But that is true in so far, indeed, as no
|
||
artist ever expressed more than one thing under different aspects.
|
||
The instantaneous perfection of art, the necessity for its renewal—
|
||
this is true only through a preconceived notion. For the work of art
|
||
likewise is a construction and everyone knows how monotonous
|
||
the great creators can be. For the same reason as the thinker, the
|
||
artist commits himself and becomes himself in his work. That
|
||
osmosis raises the most important of aesthetic problems.
|
||
Moreover, to anyone who is convinced of the mind’s singleness of
|
||
purpose, nothing is more futile than these distinctions based on
|
||
methods and objects. There are no frontiers between the disciplines
|
||
that man sets himself for understanding and loving. They interlock,
|
||
and the same anxiety merges them.
|
||
It is necessary to state this to begin with. For an absurd work of
|
||
art to be possible, thought in its most lucid form must be involved
|
||
in it. But at the same time thought must not be apparent except as
|
||
the regulating intelligence. This paradox can be explained
|
||
according to the absurd. The work of art is born of the
|
||
intelligence’s refusal to reason the concrete. It marks the triumph
|
||
of the carnal. It is lucid thought that provokes it, but in that very
|
||
act that thought repudiates itself. It will not yield to the temptation
|
||
of adding to what is described a deeper meaning that it knows to be
|
||
illegitimate. The work of art embodies a drama of the intelligence,
|
||
but it proves this only indirectly. The absurd work requires an artist
|
||
conscious of these limitations and an art in which the concrete
|
||
signifies nothing more than itself. It cannot be the end, the
|
||
meaning, and the consolation of a life. Creating or not creating
|
||
changes nothing. The absurd creator does not prize his work. He
|
||
could repudiate it. He does sometimes repudiate it. An Abyssinia
|
||
suffices for this, as in the case of Rimbaud.
|
||
At the same time a rule of aesthetics can be seen in this. The
|
||
true work of art is always on the human scale. It is essentially the
|
||
one that says “less.” There is a certain relationship between the
|
||
global experience of the artist and the work that reflects that
|
||
experience, between Wilhelm Meister and Goethe’s maturity. That
|
||
relationship is bad when the work aims to give the whole
|
||
experience in the lace-paper of an explanatory literature. That
|
||
relationship is good when the work is but a piece cut out of
|
||
experience, a facet of the diamond in which the inner luster is
|
||
epitomized without being limited. In the first case there is
|
||
overloading and pretension to the eternal. In the second, a fecund
|
||
work because of a whole implied experience, the wealth of which
|
||
is suspected. The problem for the absurd artist is to acquire this
|
||
savoir-vivre which transcends savoir-faire. And in the end, the
|
||
great artist under this climate is, above all, a great living being, it
|
||
being understood that living in this case is just as much
|
||
experiencing as reflecting. The work then embodies an intellectual
|
||
drama. The absurd work illustrates thought’s renouncing of its
|
||
prestige and its resignation to being no more than the intelligence
|
||
that works up appearances and covers with images what has no
|
||
reason. If the world were clear, art would not exist.
|
||
I am not speaking here of the arts of form or color in which
|
||
description alone prevails in its splendid modesty.[18] Expression
|
||
begins where thought ends. Those adolescents with empty
|
||
eyesockets who people temples and museums—their philosophy
|
||
has been expressed in gestures. For an absurd man it is more
|
||
educative than all libraries. Under another aspect the same is true
|
||
for music. If any art is devoid of lessons, it is certainly music. It is
|
||
too closely related to mathematics not to have borrowed their
|
||
gratuitousness. That game the mind plays with itself according to
|
||
set and measured laws takes place in the sonorous compass that
|
||
belongs to us and beyond which the vibrations nevertheless meet in
|
||
an inhuman universe. There is no purer sensation. These examples
|
||
are too easy. The absurd man recognizes as his own these
|
||
harmonies and these forms.
|
||
But I should like to speak here of a work in which the
|
||
temptation to explain remains greatest, in which illusion offers
|
||
itself automatically, in which conclusion is almost inevitable. I
|
||
mean fictional creation. I propose to inquire whether or not the
|
||
absurd can hold its own there.
|
||
* * *
|
||
To think is first of all to create a world (or to limit one’s own
|
||
world, which comes to the same thing). It is starting out from the
|
||
basic disagreement that separates man from his experience in order
|
||
to find a common ground according to one’s nostalgia, a universe
|
||
hedged with reasons or lighted up with analogies but which, in any
|
||
case, gives an opportunity to rescind the unbearable divorce. The
|
||
philosopher, even if he is Kant, is a creator. He has his characters,
|
||
his symbols, and his secret action. He has his plot endings. On the
|
||
contrary, the lead taken by the novel over poetry and the essay
|
||
merely represents, despite appearances, a greater intellectualiza-
|
||
tion of the art. Let there be no mistake about it; I am speaking of
|
||
the greatest. The fecundity and the importance of a literary form
|
||
are often measured by the trash it contains. The number of bad
|
||
novels must not make us forget the value of the best. These,
|
||
indeed, carry with them their universe. The novel has its logic, its
|
||
reasonings, its intuition, and its postulates. It also has its
|
||
requirements of clarity.[19]
|
||
The classical opposition of which I was speaking above is even
|
||
less justified in this particular case. It held in the time when it was
|
||
easy to separate philosophy from its authors. Today when thought
|
||
has ceased to lay claim to the universal, when its best history
|
||
would be that of its repentances, we know that the system, when it
|
||
is worth while, cannot be separated from its author. The Ethics
|
||
itself, in one of its aspects, is but a long and reasoned personal
|
||
confession. Abstract thought at last returns to its prop of flesh.
|
||
And, likewise, the fictional activities of the body and of the
|
||
passions are regulated a little more according to the requirements
|
||
of a vision of the world. The writer has given up telling “stories”
|
||
and creates his universe. The great novelists are philosophical
|
||
novelists—that is, the contrary of thesis-writers. For instance,
|
||
Balzac, Sade, Melville, Stendhal, Dostoevsky, Proust, Malraux,
|
||
Kafka, to cite but a few.
|
||
But in fact the preference they have shown for writing in
|
||
images rather than in reasoned arguments is revelatory of a certain
|
||
thought that is common to them all, convinced of the uselessness
|
||
of any principle of explanation and sure of the educative message
|
||
of perceptible appearance. They consider the work of art both as an
|
||
end and a beginning. It is the outcome of an often unexpressed
|
||
philosophy, its illustration and its consummation. But it is
|
||
complete only through the implications of that philosophy. It
|
||
justifies at last that variant of an old theme that a little thought
|
||
estranges from life whereas much thought reconciles to life.
|
||
Incapable of refining the real, thought pauses to mimic it. The
|
||
novel in question is the instrument of that simultaneously relative
|
||
and inexhaustible knowledge, so like that of love. Of love, fictional
|
||
creation has the initial wonder and the fecund rumination.
|
||
***
|
||
These at least are the charms I see in it at the outset. But I saw
|
||
them likewise in those princes of humiliated thought whose
|
||
suicides I was later able to witness.
|
||
What interests me, indeed, is knowing and describing the force
|
||
that leads them back toward the common path of illusion. The
|
||
same method will consequently help me here. The fact of having
|
||
already utilized it will allow me to shorten my argument and to
|
||
sum it up without delay in a particular example. I want to know
|
||
whether, accepting a life without appeal, one can also agree to
|
||
work and create without appeal and what is the way leading to
|
||
these liberties. I want to liberate my universe of its phantoms and
|
||
to people it solely with flesh-and-blood truths whose presence I
|
||
cannot deny. I can perform absurd work, choose the creative
|
||
attitude rather than another. But an absurd attitude, if it is to remain
|
||
so, must remain aware of its gratuitousness. So it is with the work
|
||
of art. If the commandments of the absurd are not respected, if the
|
||
work does not illustrate divorce and revolt, if it sacrifices to
|
||
illusions and arouses hope, it ceases to be gratuitous. I can no
|
||
longer detach myself from it. My life may find a meaning in it, but
|
||
that is trifling. It ceases to be that exercise in detachment and
|
||
passion which crowns the splendor and futility of a man’s life.
|
||
In the creation in which the temptation to explain is the
|
||
strongest, can one overcome that temptation? In the fictional world
|
||
in which awareness of the real world is keenest, can I remain
|
||
faithful to the absurd without sacrificing to the desire to judge? So
|
||
many questions to be taken into consideration in a last effort. It
|
||
must be already clear what they signify. They are the last scruples
|
||
of an awareness that fears to forsake its initial and difficult lesson
|
||
in favor of a final illusion. What holds for creation, looked upon as
|
||
one of the possible attitudes for the man conscious of the absurd,
|
||
holds for all the styles of life open to him. The conqueror or the
|
||
actor, the creator or Don Juan may forget that their exercise in
|
||
living could not do without awareness of its mad character. One
|
||
becomes accustomed so quickly. A man wants to earn money in
|
||
order to be happy, and his whole effort and the best of a life are
|
||
devoted to the earning of that money. Happiness is forgotten; the
|
||
means are taken for the end. Likewise, the whole effort of this
|
||
conqueror will be diverted to ambition, which was but a way
|
||
toward a greater life. Don Juan in turn will likewise yield to his
|
||
fate, be satisfied with that existence whose nobility is of value only
|
||
through revolt. For one it is awareness and for the other, revolt; in
|
||
both cases the absurd has disappeared. There is so much stubborn
|
||
hope in the human heart. The most destitute men often end up by
|
||
accepting illusion. That approval prompted by the need for peace
|
||
inwardly parallels the existential consent. There are thus gods of
|
||
light and idols of mud. But it is essential to find the middle path
|
||
leading to the faces of man.
|
||
So far, the failures of the absurd exigence have best informed
|
||
us as to what it is. In the same way, if we are to be informed, it will
|
||
suffice to notice that fictional creation can present the same
|
||
ambiguity as certain philosophies. Hence I can choose as
|
||
illustration a work comprising everything that denotes awareness
|
||
of the absurd, having a clear starting-point and a lucid climate. Its
|
||
consequences will enlighten us. If the absurd is not respected in it,
|
||
we shall know by what expedient illusion enters in. A particular
|
||
example, a theme, a creator’s fidelity will suffice, then. This
|
||
involves the same analysis that has already been made at greater
|
||
length.
|
||
I shall examine a favorite theme of Dostoevsky. I might just as
|
||
well have studied other works.[20] But in this work the problem is
|
||
treated directly, in the sense of nobility and emotion, as for the
|
||
existential philosophies already discussed. This parallelism serves
|
||
my purpose.
|
||
Kirilov
|
||
All of Dostoevsky’s heroes question themselves as to the
|
||
meaning of life. In this they are modern: they do not fear ridicule.
|
||
What distinguishes modern sensibility from classical sensibility is
|
||
that the latter thrives on moral problems and the former on
|
||
metaphysical problems. In Dostoevsky’s novels the question is
|
||
propounded with such intensity that it can only invite extreme
|
||
solutions. Existence is illusory or it is eternal. If Dostoevsky were
|
||
satisfied with this inquiry, he would be a philosopher. But he
|
||
illustrates the consequences that such intellectual pastimes may
|
||
have in a man’s life, and in this regard he is an artist. Among those
|
||
consequences, his attention is arrested particularly by the last one,
|
||
which he himself calls logical suicide in his Diary of a Writer. In
|
||
the installments for December 1876, indeed, he imagines the
|
||
reasoning of “logical suicide.” Convinced that human existence is
|
||
an utter absurdity for anyone without faith in immortality, the
|
||
desperate man comes to the following conclusions:
|
||
“Since in reply to my questions about happiness, I am told,
|
||
through the intermediary of my consciousness, that I cannot be
|
||
happy except in harmony with the great all, which I cannot
|
||
conceive and shall never be in a position to conceive, it is evident
|
||
...”
|
||
“Since, finally, in this connection, I assume both the role of the
|
||
plaintiff and that of the defendant, of the accused and of the judge,
|
||
and since I consider this comedy perpetrated by nature altogether
|
||
stupid, and since I even deem it humiliating for me to deign to play
|
||
it ...”
|
||
“In my indisputable capacity of plaintiff and defendant, of
|
||
judge and accused, I condemn that nature which, with such
|
||
impudent nerve, brought me into being in order to suffer—I
|
||
condemn it to be annihilated with me.”
|
||
There remains a little humor in that position. This suicide kills
|
||
himself because, on the metaphysical plane, he is vexed. In a
|
||
certain sense he is taking his revenge. This is his way of proving
|
||
that he “will not be had.” It is known, however, that the same
|
||
theme is embodied, but with the most wonderful generality, in
|
||
Kirilov of The Possessed, likewise an advocate of logical suicide.
|
||
Kirilov the engineer declares somewhere that he wants to take his
|
||
own life because it “is his idea.” Obviously the word must be taken
|
||
in its proper sense. It is for an idea, a thought, that he is getting
|
||
ready for death. This is the superior suicide. Progressively, in a
|
||
series of scenes in which Kirilov’s mask is gradually illuminated,
|
||
the fatal thought driving him is revealed to us. The engineer, in
|
||
fact, goes back to the arguments of the Diary. He feels that God is
|
||
necessary and that he must exist. But he knows that he does not
|
||
and cannot exist. “Why do you not realize,” he exclaims, “that this
|
||
is sufficient reason for killing oneself?” That attitude involves
|
||
likewise for him some of the absurd consequences. Through
|
||
indifference he accepts letting his suicide be used to the advantage
|
||
of a cause he despises. “I decided last night that I didn’t care.” And
|
||
finally he prepares his deed with a mixed feeling of revolt and
|
||
freedom. “I shall kill myself in order to assert my insubordination,
|
||
my new and dreadful liberty.” It is no longer a question of revenge,
|
||
but of revolt. Kirilov is consequently an absurd character—yet
|
||
with this essential reservation: he kills himself. But he himself
|
||
explains this contradiction, and in such a way that at the same time
|
||
he reveals the absurd secret in all its purity. In truth, he adds to his
|
||
fatal logic an extraordinary ambition which gives the character its
|
||
full perspective: he wants to kill himself to become god.
|
||
The reasoning is classic in its clarity. If God does not exist,
|
||
Kirilov is god. If God does not exist, Kirilov must kill himself.
|
||
Kirilov must therefore kill himself to become god. That logic is
|
||
absurd, but it is what is needed. The interesting thing, however, is
|
||
to give a meaning to that divinity brought to earth. That amounts to
|
||
clarifying the premise: “If God does not exist, I am god,” which
|
||
still remains rather obscure. It is important to note at the outset that
|
||
the man who flaunts that mad claim is indeed of this world. He
|
||
performs his gymnastics every morning to preserve his health. He
|
||
is stirred by the joy of Chatov recovering his wife. On a sheet of
|
||
paper to be found after his death he wants to draw a face sticking
|
||
out his tongue at “them.” He is childish and irascible, passionate,
|
||
methodical, and sensitive. Of the superman he has nothing but the
|
||
logic and the obsession, whereas of man he has the whole
|
||
catalogue. Yet it is he who speaks calmly of his divinity. He is not
|
||
mad, or else Dostoevsky is. Consequently it is not a
|
||
megalomaniac’s illusion that excites him. And taking the words in
|
||
their specific sense would, in this instance, be ridiculous.
|
||
Kirilov himself helps us to understand. In reply to a question
|
||
from Stavrogin, he makes clear that he is not talking of a god-man.
|
||
It might be thought that this springs from concern to distinguish
|
||
himself from Christ. But in reality it is a matter of annexing Christ.
|
||
Kirilov in fact fancies for a moment that Jesus at his death did not
|
||
find himself in Paradise. He found out then that his torture had
|
||
been useless. “The laws of nature,” says the engineer, “made
|
||
Christ live in the midst of falsehood and die for a falsehood.”
|
||
Solely in this sense Jesus indeed personifies the whole human
|
||
drama. He is the complete man, being the one who realized the
|
||
most absurd condition. He is not the God-man but the man-god.
|
||
And, like him, each of us can be crucified and victimized—and is
|
||
to a certain degree.
|
||
The divinity in question is therefore altogether terrestrial. “For
|
||
three years,” says Kirilov, “I sought the attribute of my divinity
|
||
and I have found it. The attribute of my divinity is independence.”
|
||
Now can be seen the meaning of Kirilov’s premise: “If God does
|
||
not exist, I am god.” To become god is merely to be free on this
|
||
earth, not to serve an immortal being. Above all, of course, it is
|
||
drawing all the inferences from that painful independence. If God
|
||
exists, all depends on him and we can do nothing against his will.
|
||
If he does not exist, everything depends on us. For Kirilov, as for
|
||
Nietzsche, to kill God is to become god oneself; it is to realize on
|
||
this earth the eternal life of which the Gospel speaks.[21] But if this
|
||
metaphysical crime is enough for man’s fulfillment, why add
|
||
suicide? Why kill oneself and leave this world after having won
|
||
freedom? That is contradictory. Kirilov is well aware of this, for he
|
||
adds: “If you feel that, you are a tsar and, far from killing yourself,
|
||
you will live covered with glory.” But men in general do not know
|
||
it. They do not feel “that.” As in the time of Prometheus, they
|
||
entertain blind hopes.[22] They need to be shown the way and
|
||
cannot do without preaching. Consequently, Kirilov must kill
|
||
himself out of love for humanity. He must show his brothers a
|
||
royal and difficult path on which he will be the first. It is a
|
||
pedagogical suicide. Kirilov sacrifices himself, then. But if he is
|
||
crucified, he will not be victimized. He remains the man-god,
|
||
convinced of a death without future, imbued with evangelical
|
||
melancholy. “I,” he says, “am unhappy because I am obliged to
|
||
assert my freedom.”
|
||
But once he is dead and men are at last enlightened, this earth
|
||
will be peopled with tsars and lighted up with human glory.
|
||
Kirilov’s pistol shot will be the signal for the last revolution. Thus,
|
||
it is not despair that urges him to death, but love of his neighbor
|
||
for his own sake. Before terminating in blood an indescribable
|
||
spiritual adventure, Kirilov makes a remark as old as human
|
||
suffering: “All is well.”
|
||
This theme of suicide in Dostoevsky, then, is indeed an absurd
|
||
theme. Let us merely note before going on that Kirilov reappears in
|
||
other characters who themselves set in motion additional absurd
|
||
themes. Stavrogin and Ivan Karamazov try out the absurd truths in
|
||
practical life. They are the ones liberated by Kirilov’s death. They
|
||
try their skill at being tsars. Stavrogin leads an “ironic” life, and it
|
||
is well known in what regard. He arouses hatred around him. And
|
||
yet the key to the character is found in his farewell letter: “I have
|
||
not been able to detest anything.” He is a tsar in indifference. Ivan
|
||
is likewise by refusing to surrender the royal powers of the mind.
|
||
To those who, like his brother, prove by their lives that it is
|
||
essential to humiliate oneself in order to believe, he might reply
|
||
that the condition is shameful. His key word is: “Everything is
|
||
permitted,” with the appropriate shade of melancholy. Of course,
|
||
like Nietzsche, the most famous of God’s assassins, he ends in
|
||
madness. But this is a risk worth running, and, faced with such
|
||
tragic ends, the essential impulse of the absurd mind is to ask:
|
||
“What does that prove?”
|
||
* * *
|
||
Thus the novels, like the Diary, propound the absurd question.
|
||
They establish logic unto death, exaltation, “dreadful” freedom, the
|
||
glory of the tsars become human. All is well, everything is
|
||
permitted, and nothing is hateful—these are absurd judgments. But
|
||
what an amazing creation in which those creatures of fire and ice
|
||
seem so familiar to us. The passionate world of indifference that
|
||
rumbles in their hearts does not seem at all monstrous to us. We
|
||
recognize in it our everyday anxieties. And probably no one so
|
||
much as Dostoevsky has managed to give the absurd world such
|
||
familiar and tormenting charms.
|
||
Yet what is his conclusion? Two quotations will show the
|
||
complete metaphysical reversal that leads the writer to other
|
||
revelations. The argument of the one who commits logical suicide
|
||
having provoked protests from the critics, Dostoevsky in the
|
||
following installments of the Diary amplifies his position and
|
||
concludes thus: “If faith in immortality is so necessary to the
|
||
human being (that without it he comes to the point of killing
|
||
himself), it must therefore be the normal state of humanity. Since
|
||
this is the case, the immortality of the human soul exists without
|
||
any doubt.” Then again in the last pages of his last novel, at the
|
||
conclusion of that gigantic combat with God, some children ask
|
||
Aliocha: “Karamazov, is it true what religion says, that we shall
|
||
rise from the dead, that we shall see one another again?” And
|
||
Aliocha answers: “Certainly, we shall see one another again, we
|
||
shall joyfully tell one another everything that has happened.’’
|
||
Thus Kirilov, Stavrogin, and Ivan are defeated. The Brothers
|
||
Karamazov replies to The Possessed. And it is indeed a conclusion.
|
||
Aliocha’s case is not ambiguous, as is that of Prince Muichkin. Ill,
|
||
the latter lives in a perpetual present, tinged with smiles and
|
||
indifference, and that blissful state might be the eternal life of
|
||
which the Prince speaks. On the contrary, Aliocha clearly says:
|
||
“We shall meet again.” There is no longer any question of suicide
|
||
and of madness. What is the use, for anyone who is sure of
|
||
immortality and of its joys? Man exchanges his divinity for
|
||
happiness. “We shall joyfully tell one another everything that has
|
||
happened.” Thus again Kirilov’s pistol rang out somewhere in
|
||
Russia, but the world continued to cherish its blind hopes. Men did
|
||
not understand “that.”
|
||
Consequently, it is not an absurd novelist addressing us, but an
|
||
existential novelist. Here, too, the leap is touching and gives its
|
||
nobility to the art that inspires it. It is a stirring acquiescence,
|
||
riddled with doubts, uncertain and ardent. Speaking of The
|
||
Brothers Karamazov, Dostoevsky wrote: “The chief question that
|
||
will be pursued throughout this book is the very one from which I
|
||
have suffered consciously or unconsciously all life long: the
|
||
existence of God.” It is hard to believe that a novel sufficed to
|
||
transform into joyful certainty the suffering of a lifetime. One
|
||
commentator[23] correctly pointed out that Dostoevsky is on Ivan’s
|
||
side and that the affirmative chapters took three months of effort
|
||
whereas what he called “the blasphemies” were written in three
|
||
weeks in a state of excitement. There is not one of his characters
|
||
who does not have that thorn in the flesh, who does not aggravate
|
||
it or seek a remedy for it in sensation or immortality.[24] In any
|
||
case, let us remain with this doubt. Here is a work which, in a
|
||
chiaroscuro more gripping than the light of day, permits us to seize
|
||
man’s struggle against his hopes. Having reached the end, the
|
||
creator makes his choice against his characters. That contradiction
|
||
thus allows us to make a distinction. It is not an absurd work that is
|
||
involved here, but a work that propounds the absurd problem.
|
||
Dostoevsky’s reply is humiliation, “shame” according to
|
||
Stavrogin. An absurd work, on the contrary, does not provide a
|
||
reply; that is the whole difference. Let us note this carefully in
|
||
conclusion: what contradicts the absurd in that work is not its
|
||
Christian character, but rather its announcing a future life. It is
|
||
possible to be Christian and absurd. There are examples of
|
||
Christians who do not believe in a future life. In regard to the work
|
||
of art, it should therefore be possible to define one of the directions
|
||
of the absurd analysis that could have been anticipated in the
|
||
preceding pages. It leads to propounding “the absurdity of the
|
||
Gospel.” It throws light upon this idea, fertile in repercussions, that
|
||
convictions do not prevent incredulity. On the contrary, it is easy
|
||
to see that the author of The Possessed, familiar with these paths,
|
||
in conclusion took a quite different way. The surprising reply of
|
||
the creator to his characters, of Do-stoevsky to Kirilov, can indeed
|
||
be summed up thus: existence is illusory and it is eternal.
|
||
Ephemeral Creation
|
||
At this point I perceive, therefore, that hope cannot be eluded
|
||
forever and that it can beset even those who wanted to be free of it.
|
||
This is the interest I find in the works discussed up to this point. I
|
||
could, at least in the realm of creation, list some truly absurd
|
||
works.[25] But everything must have a beginning. The object of this
|
||
quest is a certain fidelity. The Church has been so harsh with
|
||
heretics only because she deemed that there is no worse enemy
|
||
than a child who has gone astray. But the record of Gnostic
|
||
effronteries and the persistence of Manichean currents have
|
||
contributed more to the construction of orthodox dogma than all
|
||
the prayers. With due allowance, the same is true of the absurd.
|
||
One recognizes one’s course by discovering the paths that stray
|
||
from it. At the very conclusion of the absurd reasoning, in one of
|
||
the attitudes dictated by its logic, it is not a matter of indifference
|
||
to find hope coming back in under one of its most touching guises.
|
||
That shows the difficulty of the absurd ascesis. Above all, it shows
|
||
the necessity of unfailing alertness and thus confirms the general
|
||
plan of this essay.
|
||
But if it is still too early to list absurd works, at least a
|
||
conclusion can be reached as to the creative attitude, one of those
|
||
which can complete absurd existence. Art can never be so well
|
||
served as by a negative thought. Its dark and humiliated
|
||
proceedings are as necessary to the understanding of a great work
|
||
as black is to white. To work and create “for nothing,” to sculpture
|
||
in clay, to know that one’s creation has no future, to see one’s
|
||
work destroyed in a day while being aware that fundamentally this
|
||
has no more importance than building for centuries—this is the
|
||
difficult wisdom that absurd thought sanctions. Performing these
|
||
two tasks simultaneously, negating on the one hand and
|
||
magnifying on the other, is the way open to the absurd creator. He
|
||
must give the void its colors.
|
||
This leads to a special conception of the work of art. Too often
|
||
the work of a creator is looked upon as a series of isolated
|
||
testimonies. Thus, artist and man of letters are confused. A
|
||
profound thought is in a constant state of becoming; it adopts the
|
||
experience of a life and assumes its shape, likewise, a man’s sole
|
||
creation is strengthened in its successive and multiple aspects: his
|
||
works. One after another, they complement one an-other, correct or
|
||
overtake one another, contradict one another too. If something
|
||
brings creation to an end, it is not the victorious and illusory cry of
|
||
the blinded artist: “I have said everything,” but the death of the
|
||
creator which closes his experience and the book of his genius.
|
||
That effort, that superhuman consciousness are not necessarily
|
||
apparent to the reader. There is no mystery in human creation. Will
|
||
performs this miracle. But at least there is no true creation without
|
||
a secret. To be sure, a succession of works can be but a series of
|
||
approximations of the same thought. But it is possible to conceive
|
||
of another type of creator proceeding by juxtaposition. Their works
|
||
may seem to be devoid of interrelations. To a certain degree, they
|
||
are contradictory.
|
||
But viewed all together, they resume their natural grouping.
|
||
From death, for instance, they derive their definitive significance.
|
||
They receive their most obvious light from the very life of their
|
||
author. At the moment of death, the succession of his works is but
|
||
a collection of failures. But if those failures all have the same
|
||
resonance, the creator has managed to repeat the image of his own
|
||
condition, to make the air echo with the sterile secret he possesses.
|
||
The effort to dominate is considerable here. But human
|
||
intelligence is up to much more. It will merely indicate clearly the
|
||
voluntary aspect of creation. Elsewhere I have brought out the fact
|
||
that human will had no other purpose than to maintain awareness.
|
||
But that could not do without discipline. Of all the schools of
|
||
patience and lucidity, creation is the most effective. It is also the
|
||
staggering evidence of man’s sole dignity: the dogged revolt
|
||
against his condition, perseverance in an effort considered sterile.
|
||
It calls for a daily effort, self-mastery, a precise estimate of the
|
||
limits of truth, measure, and strength. It constitutes an ascesis. All
|
||
that “for nothing,” in order to repeat and mark time. But perhaps
|
||
the great work of art has less importance in itself than in the ordeal
|
||
it demands of a man and the opportunity it provides him of
|
||
overcoming his phantoms and approaching a little closer to his
|
||
naked reality.
|
||
* * *
|
||
Let there be no mistake in aesthetics. It is not patient inquiry,
|
||
the unceasing, sterile illustration of a thesis that I am calling for
|
||
here. Quite the contrary, if I have made myself clearly understood.
|
||
The thesis-novel, the work that proves, the most hateful of all, is
|
||
the one that most often is inspired by a smug thought. You
|
||
demonstrate the truth you feel sure of possessing. But those are
|
||
ideas one launches, and ideas are the contrary of thought. Those
|
||
creators are philosophers, ashamed of themselves. Those I am
|
||
speaking of or whom I imagine are, on the contrary, lucid thinkers.
|
||
At a certain point where thought turns back on itself, they raise up
|
||
the images of their works like the obvious symbols of a limited,
|
||
mortal, and rebellious thought.
|
||
They perhaps prove something. But those proofs are ones that
|
||
the novelists provide for themselves rather than for the world in
|
||
general. The essential is that the novelists should triumph in the
|
||
concrete and that this constitute their nobility. This wholly carnal
|
||
triumph has been prepared for them by a thought in which abstract
|
||
powers have been humiliated. When they are completely so, at the
|
||
same time the flesh makes the creation shine forth in all its absurd
|
||
luster. After all, ironic philosophies produce passionate works.
|
||
Any thought that abandons unity glorifies diversity. And
|
||
diversity is the home of art. The only thought to liberate the mind
|
||
is that which leaves it alone, certain of its limits and of its
|
||
impending end. No doctrine tempts it. It awaits the ripening of the
|
||
work and of life. Detached from it, the work will once more give a
|
||
barely muffled voice to a soul Forever freed from hope. Or it will
|
||
give voice to nothing if the creator, tired of his activity, intends to
|
||
turn away. That is equivalent.
|
||
* * *
|
||
Thus, I ask of absurd creation what I required from thought—
|
||
revolt, freedom, and diversity. Later on it will manifest its utter
|
||
futility. In that daily effort in which intelligence and passion
|
||
mingle and delight each other, the absurd man discovers a
|
||
discipline that will make up the greatest of his strengths. The
|
||
required diligence, the doggedness and lucidity thus resemble the
|
||
conqueror’s attitude. To create is likewise to give a shape to one’s
|
||
fate. For all these characters, their work defines them at least as
|
||
much as it is defined by them. The actor taught us this: there is no
|
||
frontier between being and appearing.
|
||
Let me repeat. None of all this has any real meaning. On the
|
||
way to that liberty, there is still a progress to be made. The final
|
||
effort for these related minds, creator or conqueror, is to manage to
|
||
free themselves also from their undertakings: succeed in granting
|
||
that the very work, whether it be conquest, love, or creation, may
|
||
well not be; consummate thus the utter futility of any individual
|
||
life. Indeed, that gives them more freedom in the realization of that
|
||
work, just as becoming aware of the absurdity of life authorized
|
||
them to plunge into it with every excess.
|
||
All that remains is a fate whose outcome alone is fatal. Outside
|
||
of that single fatality of death, everything, joy or happiness, is
|
||
liberty. A world remains of which man is the sole master. What
|
||
bound him was the illusion of another world. The outcome of his
|
||
thought, ceasing to be renunciatory, flowers in images. It frolics—
|
||
in myths, to be sure, but myths with no other depth than that of
|
||
human suffering and, like it, inexhaustible. Not the divine fable
|
||
that amuses and blinds, but the terrestrial face, gesture, and drama
|
||
in which are summed up a difficult wisdom and an ephemeral
|
||
passion.
|
||
The Myth Of Sisyphus
|
||
The gods had condemned Sisyphus to ceaselessly rolling a rock
|
||
to the top of a mountain, whence the stone would fall back of its
|
||
own weight. They had thought with some reason that there is no
|
||
more dreadful punishment than futile and hopeless labor.
|
||
If one believes Homer, Sisyphus was the wisest and most
|
||
prudent of mortals. According to another tradition, however, he
|
||
was disposed to practice the profession of highwayman. I see no
|
||
contradiction in this. Opinions differ as to the reasons why he
|
||
became the futile laborer of the underworld. To begin with, he is
|
||
accused of a certain levity in regard to the gods. He stole their
|
||
secrets. AEgina, the daughter of AEsopus, was carried off by
|
||
Jupiter. The father was shocked by that disappearance and
|
||
complained to Sisyphus. He, who knew of the abduction, offered
|
||
to tell about it on condition that AEsopus would give water to the
|
||
citadel of Corinth. To the celestial thunderbolts he preferred the
|
||
benediction of water. He was punished for this in the underworld.
|
||
Homer tells us also that Sisyphus had put Death in chains. Pluto
|
||
could not endure the sight of his deserted, silent empire. He
|
||
dispatched the god of war, who liberated Death from the hands of
|
||
her conqueror.
|
||
It is said also that Sisyphus, being near to death, rashly wanted
|
||
to test his wife’s love. He ordered her to cast his unburied body
|
||
into the middle of the public square. Sisyphus woke up in the
|
||
underworld. And there, annoyed by an obedience so contrary to
|
||
human love, he obtained from Pluto permission to return to earth in
|
||
order to chastise his wife. But when he had seen again the face of
|
||
this world, enjoyed water and sun, warm stones and the sea, he no
|
||
longer wanted to go back to the infernal darkness. Recalls, signs of
|
||
anger, warnings were of no avail. Many years more he lived facing
|
||
the curve of the gulf, the sparkling sea, and the smiles of earth. A
|
||
decree of the gods was necessary. Mercury came and seized the
|
||
impudent man by the collar and, snatching him from his joys, led
|
||
him forcibly back to the underworld, where his rock was ready for
|
||
him.
|
||
You have already grasped that Sisyphus is the absurd hero. He
|
||
is, as much through his passions as through his torture. His scorn
|
||
of the gods, his hatred of death, and his passion for life won him
|
||
that unspeakable penalty in which the whole being is exerted
|
||
toward accomplishing nothing. This is the price that must be paid
|
||
for the passions of this earth. Nothing is told us about Sisyphus in
|
||
the underworld. Myths are made for the imagination to breathe life
|
||
into them. As for this myth, one sees merely the whole effort of a
|
||
body straining to raise the huge stone, to roll it and push it up a
|
||
slope a hundred times over; one sees the face screwed up, the
|
||
cheek tight against the stone, the shoulder bracing the clay-covered
|
||
mass, the foot wedging it, the fresh start with arms outstretched,
|
||
the wholly human security of two earth-clotted hands. At the very
|
||
end of his long effort measured by skyless space and time without
|
||
depth, the purpose is achieved. Then Sisyphus watches the stone
|
||
rush down in a few moments toward that lower world whence he
|
||
will have to push it up again toward the summit. He goes back
|
||
down to the plain.
|
||
It is during that return, that pause, that Sisyphus interests me. A
|
||
face that toils so close to stones is already stone itself! I see that
|
||
man going back down with a heavy yet measured step toward the
|
||
torment of which he will never know the end. That hour like a
|
||
breathing-space which returns as surely as his suffering, that is the
|
||
hour of consciousness. At each of those moments when he leaves
|
||
the heights and gradually sinks toward the lairs of the gods, he is
|
||
superior to his fate. He is stronger than his rock.
|
||
If this myth is tragic, that is because its hero is conscious.
|
||
Where would his torture be, indeed, if at every step the hope of
|
||
succeeding upheld him? The workman of today works every day in
|
||
his life at the same tasks, and this fate is no less absurd. But it is
|
||
tragic only at the rare moments when it becomes conscious.
|
||
Sisyphus, proletarian of the gods, powerless and rebellious, knows
|
||
the whole extent of his wretched condition: it is what he thinks of
|
||
during his descent. The lucidity that was to constitute his torture at
|
||
the same time crowns his victory. There is no fate that cannot be
|
||
surmounted by scorn.
|
||
* * *
|
||
If the descent is thus sometimes performed in sorrow, it can
|
||
also take place in joy. This word is not too much. Again I fancy
|
||
Sisyphus returning toward his rock, and the sorrow was in the
|
||
beginning. When the images of earth cling too tightly to memory,
|
||
when the call of happiness becomes too insistent, it happens that
|
||
melancholy rises in man’s heart: this is the rock’s victory, this is
|
||
the rock itself. The boundless grief is too heavy to bear. These are
|
||
our nights of Gethsemane. But crushing truths perish from being
|
||
acknowledged. Thus, CEdipus at the outset obeys fate without
|
||
knowing it. But from the moment he knows, his tragedy begins.
|
||
Yet at the same moment, blind and desperate, he realizes that the
|
||
only bond linking him to the world is the cool hand of a girl. Then
|
||
a tremendous remark rings out: “Despite so many ordeals, my
|
||
advanced age and the nobility of my soul make me conclude that
|
||
all is well.” Sophocles’ CEdipus, like Dostoevsky’s Kirilov, thus
|
||
gives the recipe for the absurd victory. Ancient wisdom confirms
|
||
modern heroism.
|
||
One does not discover the absurd without being tempted to
|
||
write a manual of happiness. “What! by such narrow ways—?”
|
||
There is but one world, however. Happiness and the absurd are two
|
||
sons of the same earth. They are inseparable. It would be a mistake
|
||
to say that happiness necessarily springs from the absurd
|
||
discovery. It happens as well that the feeling of the absurd springs
|
||
from happiness. “I conclude that all is well,” says CEdipus, and
|
||
that remark is sacred. It echoes in the wild and limited universe of
|
||
man. It teaches that all is not, has not been, exhausted. It drives out
|
||
of this world a god who had come into it with dissatisfaction and a
|
||
preference for futile sufferings. It makes of fate a human matter,
|
||
which must be settled among men.
|
||
All Sisyphus’ silent joy is contained therein. His fate belongs
|
||
to him. His rock is his thing. Likewise, the absurd man, when he
|
||
contemplates his torment, silences all the idols. In the universe
|
||
suddenly restored to its silence, the myriad wondering little voices
|
||
of the earth rise up. Unconscious, secret calls, invitations from all
|
||
the faces, they are the necessary reverse and price of victory. There
|
||
is no sun without shadow, and it is es-sential to know the night.
|
||
The absurd man says yes and his effort will henceforth be
|
||
unceasing. If there is a personal fate, there is no higher destiny, or
|
||
at least there is but one which he concludes is inevitable and
|
||
despicable. For the rest, he knows himself to be the master of his
|
||
days. At that subtle moment when man glances backward over his
|
||
life, Sisyphus returning toward his rock, in that slight pivoting he
|
||
contemplates that series of unrelated actions which becomes his
|
||
fate, created by him, combined under his memory’s eye and soon
|
||
sealed by his death. Thus, convinced of the wholly human origin of
|
||
all that is human, a blind man eager to see who knows that the
|
||
night has no end, he is still on the go. The rock is still rolling.
|
||
I leave Sisyphus at the foot of the mountain! One always finds
|
||
one’s burden again. But Sisyphus teaches the higher fidelity that
|
||
negates the gods and raises rocks. He too concludes that all is well.
|
||
This universe henceforth without a master seems to him neither
|
||
sterile nor futile. Each atom of that stone, each mineral flake of
|
||
that night-filled mountain, in itself forms a world. The struggle
|
||
itself toward the heights is enough to fill a man’s heart. One must
|
||
imagine Sisyphus happy.
|
||
Appendix: Hope and the Absurd in the Work of Franz Kafka
|
||
The whole art of Kafka consists in forcing the reader to reread.
|
||
His endings, or his absence of endings, suggest explanations
|
||
which, however, are not revealed in clear language but, before they
|
||
seem justified, require that the story be reread from another point
|
||
of view. Sometimes there is a double possibility of interpretation,
|
||
whence appears the necessity for two readings. This is what the
|
||
author wanted. But it would be wrong to try to interpret everything
|
||
in Kafka in detail. A symbol is always in general and, however
|
||
precise its translation, an artist can restore to it only its movement:
|
||
there is no word-for-word rendering. Moreover, nothing is harder
|
||
to understand than a symbolic work. A symbol always transcends
|
||
the one who makes use of it and makes him say in reality more
|
||
than he is aware of expressing. In this regard, the surest means of
|
||
getting hold of it is not to provoke it, to begin the work without a
|
||
preconceived attitude and not to look for its hidden currents. For
|
||
Kafka in particular it is fair to agree to his rules, to approach the
|
||
drama through its externals and the novel through its form.
|
||
At first glance and for a casual reader, they are disturbing
|
||
adventures that carry off quaking and dogged characters into
|
||
pursuit of problems they never formulate. In The Trial, Joseph K.
|
||
is accused. But he doesn’t know of what. He is doubtless eager to
|
||
defend himself, but he doesn’t know why. The lawyers find his
|
||
case difficult. Meanwhile, he does not neglect to love, to eat, or to
|
||
read his paper. Then he is judged. But the courtroom is very dark.
|
||
He doesn’t understand much. He merely assumes that he is
|
||
condemned, but to what he barely wonders. At times he suspects
|
||
just the same, and he continues living. Some time later two well-
|
||
dressed and polite gentlemen come to get him and invite him to
|
||
follow them. Most courteously they lead him into a wretched
|
||
suburb, put his head on a stone, and slit his throat. Before dying the
|
||
condemned man says merely: “Like a dog.”
|
||
You see that it is hard to speak of a symbol in a tale whose
|
||
most obvious quality just happens to be naturalness. But
|
||
naturalness is a hard category to understand. There are works in
|
||
which the event seems natural to the reader. But there are others
|
||
(rarer, to be sure) in which the character considers natural what
|
||
happens to him. By an odd but obvious paradox, the more
|
||
extraordinary the character’s adventures are, the more noticeable
|
||
will be the naturalness of the story: it is in proportion to the
|
||
divergence we feel between the strangeness of a man’s life and the
|
||
simplicity with which that man accepts it. It seems that this
|
||
naturalness is Kafka’s. And, precisely, one is well aware what The
|
||
Trial means. People have spoken of an image of the human
|
||
condition. To be sure. Yet it is both simpler and more complex. I
|
||
mean that the significance of the novel is more particular and more
|
||
personal to Kafka. To a certain degree, he is the one who does the
|
||
talking, even though it is me he confesses. He lives and he is
|
||
condemned. He learns this on the first pages of the novel he is
|
||
pursuing in this world, and if he tries to cope with this, he
|
||
nonetheless does so without surprise. He will never show sufficient
|
||
astonishment at this lack of astonishment. It is by such
|
||
contradictions that the first signs of the absurd work are
|
||
recognized. The mind projects into the concrete its spiritual
|
||
tragedy. And it can do so solely by means of a perpetual paradox
|
||
which confers on colors the power to express the void and on daily
|
||
gestures the strength to translate eternal ambitions.
|
||
Likewise, The Castle is perhaps a theology in action, but it is
|
||
first of all the individual adventure of a soul in quest of its grace,
|
||
of a man who asks of this world’s objects their royal secret and of
|
||
women the signs of the god that sleeps in them. Metamorphosis, in
|
||
turn, certainly represents the horrible imagery of an ethic of
|
||
lucidity. But it is also the product of that incalculable amazement
|
||
man feels at being conscious of the beast he becomes effortlessly.
|
||
In this fundamental ambiguity lies Kafka’s secret. These perpetual
|
||
oscillations between the natural and the extraordinary, the
|
||
individual and the universal, the tragic and the everyday, the
|
||
absurd and the logical, are found throughout his work and give it
|
||
both its resonance and its meaning. These are the paradoxes that
|
||
must be enumerated, the contradictions that must be strengthened,
|
||
in order to understand the absurd work.
|
||
A symbol, indeed, assumes two planes, two worlds of ideas
|
||
and sensations, and a dictionary of correspondences between them.
|
||
This lexicon is the hardest thing to draw up. But awaking to the
|
||
two worlds brought face to face is tantamount to getting on the trail
|
||
of their secret relationships. In Kafka these two worlds are that of
|
||
everyday life on the one hand and, on the other, that of
|
||
supernatural anxiety.[26] It seems that we are witnessing here an
|
||
interminable exploitation of Nietzsche’s remark: “Great problems
|
||
are in the street.”
|
||
There is in the human condition (and this is a commonplace of
|
||
all literatures) a basic absurdity as well as an implacable nobility.
|
||
The two coincide, as is natural. Both of them are represented, let
|
||
me repeat, in the ridiculous divorce separating our spiritual
|
||
excesses and the ephemeral joys of the body. The absurd thing is
|
||
that it should be the soul of this body which it transcends so
|
||
inordinately. Whoever would like to represent this absurdity must
|
||
give it life in a series of parallel contrasts. Thus it is that Kafka
|
||
expresses tragedy by the everyday and the absurd by the logical.
|
||
An actor lends more force to a tragic character the more careful
|
||
he is not to exaggerate it. If he is moderate, the horror he inspires
|
||
will be immoderate. In this regard Greek tragedy is rich in lessons.
|
||
In a tragic work fate always makes itself felt better in the guise of
|
||
logic and naturalness. CEdipus’s fate is announced in advance. It is
|
||
decided supernaturally that he will commit the murder and the
|
||
incest. The drama’s whole effort is to show the logical system
|
||
which, from deduction to deduction, will crown the hero’s
|
||
misfortune. Merely to announce to us that uncommon fate is
|
||
scarcely horrible, because it is improbable. But if its necessity is
|
||
demonstrated to us in the framework of everyday life, society,
|
||
state, familiar emotion, then the horror is hallowed. In that revolt
|
||
that shakes man and makes him say: “That is not possible,” there is
|
||
an element of desperate certainty that “that” can be.
|
||
This is the whole secret of Greek tragedy, or at least of one of
|
||
its aspects. For there is another which, by a reverse method, would
|
||
help us to understand Kafka better. The human heart has a tiresome
|
||
tendency to label as fate only what crushes it. But happiness
|
||
likewise, in its way, is without reason, since it is inevitable.
|
||
Modern man, however, takes the credit for it himself, when he
|
||
doesn’t fail to recognize it. Much could be said, on the contrary,
|
||
about the privileged fates of Greek tragedy and those favored in
|
||
legend who, like Ulysses, in the midst of the worst adventures are
|
||
saved from themselves. It was not so easy to return to Ithaca.
|
||
What must be remembered in any case is that secret complicity
|
||
that joins the logical and the everyday to the tragic. This is why
|
||
Samsa, the hero of Metamorphosis, is a traveling salesman. This is
|
||
why the only thing that disturbs him in the strange adventure that
|
||
makes a vermin of him is that his boss will be angry at his absence.
|
||
Legs and feelers grow out on him, his spine arches up, white spots
|
||
appear on his belly and—I shall not say that this does not astonish
|
||
him, for the effect would be spoiled—but it causes him a “slight
|
||
annoyance.” The whole art of Kafka is in that distinction. In his
|
||
central work, The Castle, the details of everyday life stand out, and
|
||
yet in that strange novel in which nothing concludes and
|
||
everything begins over again, it is the essential adventure of a soul
|
||
in quest of its grace that is represented. That translation of the
|
||
problem into action, that coincidence of the general and the
|
||
particular are recognized likewise in the little artifices that belong
|
||
to every great creator. In The Trial the hero might have been
|
||
named Schmidt or Franz Kafka. But he is named Joseph K. He is
|
||
not Kafka and yet he is Kafka. He is an average European. He is
|
||
like everybody else. But he is also the entity K. who is the x of this
|
||
flesh-and-blood equation.
|
||
Likewise, if Kafka wants to express the absurd, he will make
|
||
use of consistency. You know the story of the crazy man who was
|
||
fishing in a bathtub. A doctor with ideas as to psychiatric
|
||
treatments asked him “if they were biting,” to which he received
|
||
the harsh reply: “Of course not, you fool, since this is a bathtub.”
|
||
That story belongs to the baroque type. But in it can be grasped
|
||
quite clearly to what a degree the absurd effect is linked to an
|
||
excess of logic. Kafka’s world is in truth an indescribable universe
|
||
in which man allows himself the tormenting luxury of fishing in a
|
||
bathtub, knowing that nothing will come of it.
|
||
Consequently, I recognize here a work that is absurd in its
|
||
principles. As for The Trial, for instance, I can indeed say that it is
|
||
a complete success. Flesh wins out.
|
||
Nothing is lacking, neither the unexpressed revolt (but it is
|
||
what is writing), nor lucid and mute despair (but it is what is
|
||
creating), nor that amazing freedom of manner which the
|
||
characters of the novel exemplify until their ultimate death.
|
||
* * *
|
||
Yet this world is not so closed as it seems. Into this universe
|
||
devoid of progress, Kafka is going to introduce hope in a strange
|
||
form. In this regard The Trial and The Castle do not follow the
|
||
same direction. They complement each other. The barely
|
||
perceptible progression from one to the other represents a
|
||
tremendous conquest in the realm of evasion. The Trial propounds
|
||
a problem which The Castle, to a certain degree, solves. The first
|
||
describes according to a quasi scientific method and without
|
||
concluding. The second, to a certain degree, explains. The Trial
|
||
diagnoses, and The Castle imagines a treatment. But the remedy
|
||
proposed here does not cure. It merely brings the malady back into
|
||
normal life. It helps to accept it. In a certain sense (let us think of
|
||
Kierkegaard), it makes people cherish it. The Land Surveyor K.
|
||
cannot imagine another anxiety than the one that is tormenting
|
||
him. The very people around him become attached to that void and
|
||
that nameless pain, as if suffering assumed in this case a privileged
|
||
aspect. “How I need you,” Frieda says to K. “How forsaken I feel,
|
||
since knowing you, when you are not with me.” This subtle
|
||
remedy that makes us love what crushes us and makes hope spring
|
||
up in a world without issue, this sudden “leap” through which
|
||
everything is changed, is the secret of the existential revolution and
|
||
of The Castle itself.
|
||
Few works are more rigorous in their development than The
|
||
Castle. K. is named Land Surveyor to the Castle and he arrives in
|
||
the village. But from the village to the Castle it is impossible to
|
||
communicate. For hundreds of pages K. persists in seeking his
|
||
way, makes every advance, uses trickery and expedients, never
|
||
gets angry, and with disconcerting good will tries to assume the
|
||
duties entrusted to him. Each chapter is a new frustration. And also
|
||
a new beginning. It is not logic, but consistent method. The scope
|
||
of that insistence constitutes the work’s tragic quality. When K.
|
||
telephones to the Castle, he hears confused, mingled voices, vague
|
||
laughs, distant invitations. That is enough to feed his hope, like
|
||
those few signs appearing in summer skies or those evening
|
||
anticipations which make up our reason for living. Here is found
|
||
the secret of the melancholy peculiar to Kafka. The same, in truth,
|
||
that is found in Proust’s work or in the landscape of Plotinus: a
|
||
nostalgia for a lost paradise. “I become very sad,” says Olga,
|
||
“when Barnabas tells me in the morning that he is going to the
|
||
Castle: that probably futile trip, that probably wasted day, that
|
||
probably empty hope.”
|
||
“Probably”—on this implication Kafka gambles his entire
|
||
work. But nothing avails; the quest of the eternal here is
|
||
meticulous. And those inspired automata, Kafka’s characters,
|
||
provide us with a precise image of what we should be if we were
|
||
deprived of our distractions[27] and utterly consigned to the
|
||
humiliations of the divine.
|
||
In The Castle that surrender to the everyday becomes an ethic.
|
||
The great hope of K. is to get the Castle to adopt him. Unable to
|
||
achieve this alone, his whole effort is to deserve this favor by
|
||
becoming an inhabitant of the village, by losing the status of
|
||
foreigner that everyone makes him feel. What he wants is an
|
||
occupation, a home, the life of a healthy, normal man. He can’t
|
||
stand his madness any longer. He wants to be reasonable. He wants
|
||
to cast off the peculiar curse that makes him a stranger to the
|
||
village. The episode of Frieda is significant in this regard. If he
|
||
takes as his mistress this woman who has known one of the
|
||
Castle’s officials, this is because of her past. He derives from her
|
||
something that transcends him while being aware of what makes
|
||
her forever unworthy of the Castle. This makes one think of
|
||
Kierkegaard’s strange love for Regina Olsen. In certain men, the
|
||
fire of eternity consuming them is great enough for them to burn in
|
||
it the very heart of those closest to them. The fatal mistake that
|
||
consists in giving to God what is not God’s is likewise the subject
|
||
of this episode of The Castle. But for Kafka it seems that this is not
|
||
a mistake. It is a doctrine and a “leap.” There is nothing that is not
|
||
God’s.
|
||
Even more significant is the fact that the Land Surveyor breaks
|
||
with Frieda in order to go toward the Barnabas sisters. For the
|
||
Barnabas family is the only one in the village that is utterly
|
||
forsaken by the Castle and by the village itself. Amalia, the elder
|
||
sister, has rejected the shameful propositions made her by one of
|
||
the Castle’s officials. The immoral curse that followed has forever
|
||
cast her out from the love of God. Being incapable of losing one’s
|
||
honor for God amounts to making oneself unworthy of his grace.
|
||
You recognize a theme familiar to existential philosophy: truth
|
||
contrary to morality. At this point things are far-reaching. For the
|
||
path pursued by Kafka’s hero from Frieda to the Barnabas sisters is
|
||
the very one that leads from trusting love to the deification of the
|
||
absurd. Here again Kafka’s thought runs parallel to Kierkegaard. It
|
||
is not surprising that the “Barnabas story” is placed at the end of
|
||
the book. The Land Surveyor’s last attempt is to recapture God
|
||
through what negates him, to recognize him, not according to our
|
||
categories of goodness and beauty, but behind the empty and
|
||
hideous aspects of his indifference, of his injustice, and of his
|
||
hatred. That stranger who asks the Castle to adopt him is at the end
|
||
of his voyage a little more exiled because this time he is unfaithful
|
||
to himself, forsaking morality, logic, and intellectual truths in order
|
||
to try to enter, endowed solely with his mad hope, the desert of
|
||
divine grace.[28]
|
||
***
|
||
The word “hope” used here is not ridiculous. On the contrary,
|
||
the more tragic the condition described by Kafka, the firmer and
|
||
more aggressive that hope becomes. The more truly absurd The
|
||
Trial is, the more moving and illegitimate the impassioned “leap”
|
||
of The Castle seems. But we find here again in a pure state the
|
||
paradox of existential thought as it is expressed, for instance, by
|
||
Kierkegaard: “Earthly hope must be killed; only then can one be
|
||
saved by true hope,” [29]which can be translated: “One has to have
|
||
written The Trial to undertake The Castle.”
|
||
Most of those who have spoken of Kafka have indeed defined
|
||
his work as a desperate cry with no recourse left to man. But this
|
||
calls for review. There is hope and hope. To me the optimistic
|
||
work of Henri Bordeaux seems peculiarly discouraging. This is
|
||
because it has nothing for the discriminating. Malraux’s thought,
|
||
on the other hand, is always bracing. But in these two cases neither
|
||
the same hope nor the same despair is at issue. I see merely that the
|
||
absurd work itself may lead to the infidelity I want to avoid. The
|
||
work which was but an ineffectual repetition of a sterile condition,
|
||
a lucid glorification ol the ephemeral, becomes here a cradle of
|
||
illusions. It explains, it gives a shape to hope. The creator can no
|
||
longer divorce himself from it. It is not the tragic game it was to
|
||
be. It gives a meaning to the author’s life.
|
||
It is strange in any case that works of related inspiration like
|
||
those of Kafka, Kierkegaard, or Chestov—those, in short, of
|
||
existential novelists and philosophers completely oriented toward
|
||
the Absurd and its consequences—should in the long run lead to
|
||
that tremendous cry of hope.
|
||
They embrace the God that consumes them. It is through
|
||
humility that hope enters in. For the absurd of this existence
|
||
assures them a little more of supernatural reality. If the course of
|
||
this life leads to God, there is an outcome after all. And the
|
||
perseverance, the insistence with which Kierkegaard, Chestov, and
|
||
Kafka’s heroes repeat their itineraries are a special warrant of the
|
||
uplifting power of that certainty.[30]
|
||
Kafka refuses his god moral nobility, evidence, virtue,
|
||
coherence, but only the better to fall into his arms. The absurd is
|
||
recognized, accepted, and man is resigned to it, but from then on
|
||
we know that it has ceased to be the absurd. Within the limits of
|
||
the human condition, what greater hope than the hope that allows
|
||
an escape from that condition? As I see once more, existential
|
||
thought in this regard (and contrary to current opinion) is steeped
|
||
in a vast hope. The very hope which at the time of early
|
||
Christianity and the spreading of the good news inflamed the
|
||
ancient world. But in that leap that characterizes all existential
|
||
thought, in that insistence, in that surveying of a divinity devoid of
|
||
surface, how can one fail to see the mark of a lucidity that
|
||
repudiates itself? It is merely claimed that this is pride abdicating
|
||
to save itself. Such a repudiation would be fecund. But this does
|
||
not change that. The moral value of lucidity cannot be diminished
|
||
in my eyes by calling it sterile like all pride. For a truth also, by its
|
||
very definition, is sterile. All facts are. In a world where everything
|
||
is given and nothing is explained, the fecundity of a value or of a
|
||
metaphysic is a notion devoid of meaning.
|
||
In any case, you see here in what tradition of thought Kafka’s
|
||
work takes its place. It would indeed be intelligent to consider as
|
||
inevitable the progression leading from The Trial to The Castle.
|
||
Joseph K. and the Land Surveyor K. are merely two poles that
|
||
attract Kafka.[31] I shall speak like him and say that his work is
|
||
probably not absurd. But that should not deter us from seeing its
|
||
nobility and universality. They come from the fact that he managed
|
||
to represent so fully the everyday passage from hope to grief and
|
||
from desperate wisdom to intentional blindness. His work is
|
||
universal (a really absurd work is not universal) to the extent to
|
||
which it represents the emotionally moving face of man fleeing
|
||
humanity, deriving from his contradictions reasons for believing,
|
||
reasons for hoping from his fecund despairs, and calling life his
|
||
terrifying apprenticeship in death. It is universal because its
|
||
inspiration is religious. As in all religions, man is freed of the
|
||
weight of his own life. But if I know that, if I can even admire it, I
|
||
also know that I am not seeking what is universal, but what is true.
|
||
The two may well not coincide.
|
||
This particular view will be better understood if I say that truly
|
||
hopeless thought just happens to be defined by the opposite criteria
|
||
and that the tragic work might be the work that, after all future
|
||
hope is exiled, describes the life of a happy man. The more
|
||
exciting life is, the more absurd is the idea of losing it. This is
|
||
perhaps the secret of that proud aridity felt in Nietzsche’s work. In
|
||
this connection, Nietzsche appears to be the only artist to have
|
||
derived the extreme consequences of an aesthetic of the Absurd,
|
||
inasmuch as his final message lies in a sterile and conquering
|
||
lucidity and an obstinate negation of any supernatural consolation.
|
||
The preceding should nevertheless suffice to bring out the
|
||
capital importance of Kafka in the framework of this essay. Here
|
||
we are carried to the confines of human thought. In the fullest
|
||
sense of the word, it can be said that everything in that work is
|
||
essential. In any case, it propounds the absurd problem altogether.
|
||
If one wants to compare these conclusions with our initial remarks,
|
||
the content with the form, the secret meaning of The Castle with
|
||
the natural art in which it is molded, K.’s passionate, proud quest
|
||
with the everyday setting against which it takes place, then one
|
||
will realize what may be its greatness. For if nostalgia is the mark
|
||
of the human, perhaps no one has given such flesh and volume to
|
||
these phantoms of regret. But at the same time will be sensed what
|
||
exceptional nobility the absurd work calls for, which is perhaps not
|
||
found here. If the nature of art is to bind the general to the
|
||
particular, ephemeral eternity of a drop of water to the play of its
|
||
lights, it is even truer to judge the greatness of the absurd writer by
|
||
the distance he is able to introduce between these two worlds. His
|
||
secret consists in being able to find the exact point where they
|
||
meet in their greatest disproportion.
|
||
And, to tell the truth, this geometrical locus of man and the
|
||
inhuman is seen everywhere by the pure in heart. If Faust and Don
|
||
Quixote are eminent creations of art, this is because of the
|
||
immeasurable nobilities they point out to us with their earthly
|
||
hands. Yet a moment always comes when the mind negates the
|
||
truths that those hands can touch. A moment comes when the
|
||
creation ceases to be taken tragically; it is merely taken seriously.
|
||
Then man is concerned with hope. But that is not his business. His
|
||
business is to turn away from subterfuge. Yet this is just what I
|
||
find at the conclusion of the vehement proceedings Kafka institutes
|
||
against the whole universe. His unbelievable verdict is this hideous
|
||
and upsetting world in which the very moles dare to hope.[32]
|
||
Summer In Algiers
|
||
for
|
||
JACQUES HEURGON
|
||
The loves we share with a city are often secret loves. Old
|
||
walled towns like Paris, Prague, and even Florence are closed in on
|
||
themselves and hence limit the world that belongs to them. But
|
||
Algiers (together with certain other privileged places such as cities
|
||
on the sea) opens to the sky like a mouth or a wound. In Algiers
|
||
one loves the commonplaces: the sea at the end of every street, a
|
||
certain volume of sunlight, the beauty of the race. And, as always,
|
||
in that unashamed offering there is a secret fragrance. In Paris it is
|
||
possible to be homesick for space and a beating of wings. Here at
|
||
least man is gratified in every wish and, sure of his desires, can at
|
||
last measure his possessions.
|
||
Probably one has to live in Algiers for some time in order to
|
||
realize how paralyzing an excess of nature’s bounty can be. There
|
||
is nothing here for whoever would learn, educate himself, or better
|
||
himself. This country has no lessons to teach. It neither promises
|
||
nor affords glimpses. It is satisfied to give, but in abundance. It is
|
||
completely accessible to the eyes, and you know it the moment you
|
||
enjoy it. Its pleasures are without remedy and its joys without
|
||
hope. Above all, it requires clairvoyant souls—that is, without
|
||
solace. It insists upon one’s performing an act of lucidity as one
|
||
performs an act of faith. Strange country that gives the man it
|
||
nourishes both his splendor and his misery! It is not surprising that
|
||
the sensual riches granted to a sensitive man of these regions
|
||
should coincide with the most extreme destitution. No truth fails to
|
||
carry with it its bitterness. How can one be surprised, then, if I
|
||
never feel more affection for the face of this country than amid its
|
||
poorest men?
|
||
During their entire youth men find here a life in proportion to
|
||
their beauty. Then, later on, the downhill slope and obscurity. They
|
||
wagered on the flesh, but knowing they were to lose. In Algiers
|
||
whoever is young and alive finds sanctuary and occasion for
|
||
triumphs everywhere: in the bay, the sun, the red and white games
|
||
on the seaward terraces, the flowers and sports stadiums, the cool-
|
||
legged girls. But for whoever has lost his youth there is nothing to
|
||
cling to and nowhere where melancholy can escape itself.
|
||
Elsewhere, Italian terraces, European cloisters, or the profile of the
|
||
Provencal hills—all places where man can flee his humanity and
|
||
gently liberate himself from himself. But everything here calls for
|
||
solitude and the blood of young men. Goethe on his deathbed calls
|
||
for light and this is a historic remark. At Belcourt and Bab-el-Oued
|
||
old men seated in the depths of cafes listen to the bragging of
|
||
young men with plastered hair.
|
||
Summer betrays these beginnings and ends to us in Algiers.
|
||
During those months the city is deserted. But the poor remain, and
|
||
the sky. We join the former as they go down toward the harbor and
|
||
man’s treasures: warmth of the water and the brown bodies of
|
||
women. In the evening, sated with such wealth, they return to the
|
||
oilcloth and kerosene lamp that constitute the whole setting of their
|
||
life.
|
||
In Algiers no one says “go for a swim,” but rather “indulge in a
|
||
swim.” The implications are clear. People swim in the harbor and
|
||
go to rest on the buoys. Anyone who passes near a buoy where a
|
||
pretty girl already is sunning herself shouts to his friends: “I tell
|
||
you it’s a seagull.” These are healthy amusements. They must
|
||
obviously constitute the ideal of those youths, since most of them
|
||
continue the same life in the winter, undressing every day at noon
|
||
for a frugal lunch in the sun. Not that they have read the boring
|
||
sermons of the nudists, those Protestants of the flesh (there is a
|
||
theory of the body quite as tiresome as that of the mind). But they
|
||
are simply “comfortable in the sunlight.” The importance of this
|
||
custom for our epoch can never be overestimated. For the first time
|
||
in two thousand years the body has appeared naked on beaches.
|
||
For twenty centuries men have striven to give decency to Greek
|
||
insolence and naivete, to diminish the flesh and complicate dress.
|
||
Today, despite that history, young men running on Mediterranean
|
||
beaches repeat the gestures of the athletes of Delos. And living
|
||
thus among bodies and through one’s body, one becomes aware
|
||
that it has its connotations, its life, and, to risk nonsense, a
|
||
psychology of its own.[33] The body’s evolution, like that of the
|
||
mind, has its history, its vicissitudes, its progress, and its
|
||
deficiency. With this distinction, however: color. When you
|
||
frequent the beach in summer you become aware of a simultaneous
|
||
progression of all skins from white to golden to tanned, ending up
|
||
in a tobacco color which marks the extreme limit of the effort of
|
||
transformation of which the body is capable. Above the harbor
|
||
stands the set of white cubes of the Kasbah. When you are at water
|
||
level, against the sharp while background of the Arab town the
|
||
bodies describe a copper-colored frieze. And as the month of
|
||
August progresses and the sun grows, the white of the houses
|
||
becomes more blinding and skins take on a darker warmth. How
|
||
can one fail to participate, then, in that dialogue of stone and flesh
|
||
in tune with the sun and seasons? The whole morning has been
|
||
spent in diving, in bursts of laughter amid splashing water, in
|
||
vigorous paddles around the red and black freighters (those from
|
||
Norway with all the scents of wood, those that come from
|
||
Germany full of the smell of oil, those that go up and down the
|
||
coast and smell of wine and old casks). At the hour when the sun
|
||
overflows from every corner of the sky at once, the orange canoe
|
||
loaded with brown bodies brings us home in a mad race. And
|
||
when, having suddenly interrupted the cadenced beat of the double
|
||
paddle’s bright-colored wings, we glide slowly in the calm water
|
||
of the inner harbor, how can I fail to feel that I am piloting through
|
||
the smooth waters a savage cargo of gods in whom I recognize my
|
||
brothers?
|
||
But at the other end of the city summer is already offering us,
|
||
by way of contrast, its other riches: I mean its silence and its
|
||
boredom. That silence is not always of the same quality, depending
|
||
on whether it springs from the shade or the sunlight. There is the
|
||
silence of noon on the Place du Gouvernement. In the shade of the
|
||
trees surrounding it, Arabs sell for five sous glasses of iced
|
||
lemonade flavored with orange-flowers. Their cry “Cool, cool” can
|
||
be heard across the empty square. After their cry silence again falls
|
||
under the burning sun: in the vendor’s jug the ice moves and I can
|
||
hear its tinkle. There is the silence of the siesta. In the streets of the
|
||
Marine, in front of the dirty barbershops it can be measured in the
|
||
melodious buzzing of flies behind the hollow reed curtains.
|
||
Elsewhere, in the Moorish cafes of the Kasbah the body is silent,
|
||
unable to tear itself away, to leave the glass of tea and rediscover
|
||
time with the pulsing of its own blood. But, above all, there is the
|
||
silence of summer evenings.
|
||
Those brief moments when day topples into night must be
|
||
peopled with secret signs and summons for my Algiers to be so
|
||
closely linked to them. When I spend some time far from that
|
||
town, I imagine its twilights as promises of happiness. On the hills
|
||
above the city there are paths among the mastics and olive trees.
|
||
And toward them my heart turns at such moments. I see flights of
|
||
black birds rise against the green horizon. In the sky suddenly
|
||
divested of its sun something relaxes. A whole little nation of red
|
||
clouds stretches out until it is absorbed in the air. Almost
|
||
immediately afterward appears the first star that had been seen
|
||
taking shape and consistency in the depth of the sky. And then
|
||
suddenly, all consuming, night. What exceptional quality do the
|
||
fugitive Algerian evenings possess to be able to release so many
|
||
things in me? I haven’t time to tire of that sweetness they leave on
|
||
my lips before it has disappeared into night. Is this the secret of its
|
||
persistence? This country’s affection is overwhelming and furtive.
|
||
But during the moment it is present, one’s heart at least surrenders
|
||
completely to it. At Padovani Beach the dance hall is open every
|
||
day. And in that huge rectangular box with its entire side open to
|
||
the sea, the poor young people of the neighborhood dance until
|
||
evening. Often I used to await there a moment of exceptional
|
||
beauty. During the day the hall is protected by sloping wooden
|
||
awnings. When the sun goes down they are raised. Then the hall is
|
||
filled with an odd green light born of the double shell of the sky
|
||
and the sea. When one is seated far from the windows, one sees
|
||
only the sky and, silhouetted against it, the faces of the dancers
|
||
passing in succession. Sometimes a waltz is being played, and
|
||
against the green background the black profiles whirl obstinately
|
||
like those cut-out silhouettes that are attached to a phonograph’s
|
||
turntable. Night comes rapidly after this, and with it the lights. But
|
||
I am unable to relate the thrill and secrecy that subtle instant holds
|
||
for me. I recall at least a magnificent tall girl who had danced all
|
||
afternoon. She was wearing a jasmine garland on her tight blue
|
||
dress, wet with perspiration from the small of her back to her legs.
|
||
She was laughing as she danced and throwing back her head. As
|
||
she passed the tables, she left behind her a mingled scent of
|
||
flowers and flesh. When evening came, I could no longer see her
|
||
body pressed tight to her partner, but against the sky whirled
|
||
alternating spots of white jasmine and black hair, and when she
|
||
would throw back her swelling breast I would hear her laugh and
|
||
see her partner’s profile suddenly plunge forward. I owe to such
|
||
evenings the idea I have of innocence. In any case, I learn not to
|
||
separate these creatures bursting with violent energy from the sky
|
||
where their desires whirl.
|
||
* * *
|
||
In the neighborhood movies in Algiers peppermint lozenges are
|
||
sometimes sold with, stamped in red, all that is necessary to the
|
||
awakening of love: (1) questions: “When will you marry me?” “Do
|
||
you love me?” and (2) replies: “Madly,” “Next spring.” After
|
||
having prepared the way, you pass them to your neighbor, who
|
||
answers likewise or else turns a deaf ear. At Belcourt marriages
|
||
have been arranged this way and whole lives been pledged by the
|
||
mere exchange of peppermint lozenges. And this really depicts the
|
||
childlike people of this region.
|
||
The distinguishing mark of youth is perhaps a magnificent
|
||
vocation for facile joys. But, above all, it is a haste to live that
|
||
borders on waste. At Belcourt, as at Bab-el-Oued, people get
|
||
married young. They go to work early and in ten years exhaust the
|
||
experience of a lifetime. A thirty-year-old workman has already
|
||
played all the cards in his hand. He awaits the end between his
|
||
wife and his children. His joys have been sudden and merciless, as
|
||
has been his life. One realizes that he is born of this country where
|
||
everything is given to be taken away. In that plenty and profusion
|
||
life follows the sweep of great passions, sudden, exacting, and
|
||
generous. It is not to be built up, but to be burned up. Stopping to
|
||
think and becoming better are out of the question. The notion of
|
||
hell, for instance, is merely a funny joke here. Such imaginings are
|
||
allowed only to the very virtuous. And I really think that virtue is a
|
||
meaningless word in all Algeria. Not that these men lack
|
||
principles. They have their code, and a very special one. You are
|
||
not disrespectful to your mother. You see that your wife is
|
||
respected in the street. You show consideration for a pregnant
|
||
woman. You don’t double up on an adversary, because “that looks
|
||
bad.” Whoever does not observe these elementary commandments
|
||
“is not a man,” and the question is decided. This strikes me as fair
|
||
and strong. There are still many of us who automatically observe
|
||
this code of the street, the only disinterested one I know. But at the
|
||
same time the shopkeeper’s ethics are unknown. I have always
|
||
seen faces around me filled with pity at the sight of a man between
|
||
two policemen. And before knowing whether the man had stolen,
|
||
killed his father, or was merely a nonconformist, they would say:
|
||
“The poor fellow,” or else, with a hint of admiration: “He’s a
|
||
pirate, all right.”
|
||
There are races born for pride and life. They are the ones that
|
||
nourish the strangest vocation for boredom. It is also among them
|
||
that the attitude toward death is the most repulsive. Aside from
|
||
sensual pleasure, the amusements of this race are among the
|
||
silliest. A society of bowlers and association banquets, the three-
|
||
franc movies and parish feasts have for years provided the
|
||
recreation of those over thirty. Algiers Sundays are among the
|
||
most sinister. How, then, could this race devoid of spirituality
|
||
clothe in myths the profound horror of its life? Everything related
|
||
to death is either ridiculous or hateful here. This populace without
|
||
religion and without idols dies alone after having lived in a crowd.
|
||
I know no more hideous spot than the cemetery on Boulevard Bru,
|
||
opposite one of the most beautiful landscapes in the world. An
|
||
accumulation of bad taste among the black fencings allows a
|
||
dreadful melancholy to rise from this spot where death shows her
|
||
true likeness. “Everything fades,” say the heart-shaped ex-votos,
|
||
“except memory.” And all insist on that paltry eternity provided us
|
||
cheaply by the hearts of those who loved us. The same words fit all
|
||
despairs. Addressed to the dead man, they speak to him in the
|
||
second person (our memory will never forsake you); lugubrious
|
||
pretense which attributes a body and desires to what is at best a
|
||
black liquid. Elsewhere, amid a deadly profusion of marble flowers
|
||
and birds, this bold assertion: “Never will your grave be without
|
||
flowers.” But never fear: the inscription surrounds a gilded stucco
|
||
bouquet, very time-saving for the living (like those immortelles
|
||
which owe their pompous name to the gratitude of those who still
|
||
jump onto moving buses). Inasmuch as it is essential to keep up
|
||
with the times, the classic warbler is sometimes replaced by an
|
||
astounding pearl airplane piloted by a silly angel who, without
|
||
regard for logic, is provided with an impressive pair of wings.
|
||
Yet how to bring out that these images of death are never
|
||
separated from life? Here the values are closely linked. The
|
||
favorite joke of Algerian undertakers, when driving an empty
|
||
hearse, is to shout: “Want a ride, sister?” to any pretty girls they
|
||
meet on the way. There is no objection to seeing a symbol in this,
|
||
even if somewhat untoward. It may seem blasphemous, likewise,
|
||
to reply to the announcement of a death while winking one’s left
|
||
eye: “Poor fellow, he’ll never sing again,” or, like that woman of
|
||
Oran who bad never loved her husband: “God gave him to me and
|
||
God has taken him from me.” But, all in all, I see nothing sacred in
|
||
death and am well aware, on the other hand, of the distance there is
|
||
between fear and respect. Everything here suggests the horror of
|
||
dying in a country that invites one to live. And yet it is under the
|
||
very walls of this cemetery that the young of Belcourt have their
|
||
assignations and that the girls offer themselves to kisses and
|
||
caresses.
|
||
I am well aware that such a race cannot be accepted by all.
|
||
Here intelligence has no place as in Italy. This race is indifferent to
|
||
the mind. It has a cult for and admiration of the body. Whence its
|
||
strength, its innocent cynicism, and a puerile vanity which explains
|
||
why it is so severely judged. It is commonly blamed for its
|
||
“mentality”—that is, a way of seeing and of living. And it is true
|
||
that a certain intensity of life is inseparable from injustice. Yet here
|
||
is a rate without past, without tradition, and yet not without
|
||
poetry—but a poetry whose quality I know well, harsh, carnal, far
|
||
from tenderness, that of their very sky, the only one in truth to
|
||
move me and bring me inner peace. The contrary of a civilized
|
||
nation is a creative nation. I have the mad hope that, without
|
||
knowing it perhaps, these barbarians lounging on beaches are
|
||
actually modeling the image of a culture in which the greatness of
|
||
man will at last find its true likeness. This race, wholly cast into its
|
||
present, lives without myths, without solace. It has put all its
|
||
possessions on this earth and therefore remains without defense
|
||
against death. All the gifts of physical beauty have been lavished
|
||
on it. And with them, the strange avidity that always accompanies
|
||
that wealth without future. Everything that is done here shows a
|
||
horror of stability and a disregard for the future. People are in haste
|
||
to live, and if an art were to be born here it would obey that hatred
|
||
of permanence that made the Dorians fashion their first column in
|
||
wood. And yet, yes, one can find measure as well as excess in the
|
||
violent and keen face of this race, in this summer sky with nothing
|
||
tender in it, before which all truths can be uttered and on which no
|
||
deceptive divinity has traced the signs of hope or of redemption.
|
||
Between this sky and these faces turned toward it, nothing on
|
||
which to hang a mythology, a literature, an ethic, or a religion, but
|
||
stones, flesh, stars, and those truths the hand can touch.
|
||
* * *
|
||
To feel one’s attachment to a certain region, one’s love for a
|
||
certain group of men, to know that there is always a spot where
|
||
one’s heart will feel at peace these are many certainties for a single
|
||
human life. And yet this is not enough. But at certain moments
|
||
everything yearns for that spiritual home. “Yes, we must go back
|
||
there—there, indeed.” Is there anything odd in finding on earth that
|
||
union that Plotinus longed for? Unity is expressed here in terms of
|
||
sun and sea. The heart is sensitive to it through a certain savor of
|
||
flesh which constitutes its bitterness and its grandeur. I learn that
|
||
there is no superhuman happiness, no eternity outside the sweep of
|
||
days. These paltry and essential belongings, these relative truths
|
||
are the only ones to stir me. As for the others, the “ideal” truths, I
|
||
have not enough soul to understand them. Not that one must be an
|
||
animal, but I find no meaning in the happiness of angels. I know
|
||
simply that this sky will last longer than I. And what shall I call
|
||
eternity except what will continue after my death? I am not
|
||
expressing here the creature’s satisfaction with his condition. It is
|
||
quite a different matter. It is not always easy to be a man, still less
|
||
to be a pure man. But being pure is recovering that spiritual home
|
||
where one can feel the world’s relationship, where one’s pulse-
|
||
beats coincide with the violent throbbing of the two-o’clock sun. It
|
||
is well known that one’s native land is always recognized at the
|
||
moment of losing it. For those who are too uneasy about
|
||
themselves, their native land is the one that negates them. I should
|
||
not like to be brutal or seem extravagant. But, after all, what
|
||
negates me in this life is first of all what kills me. Everything that
|
||
exalts life at the same time increases its absurdity. In the Algerian
|
||
summer I learn that one thing only is more tragic than suffering,
|
||
and that is the life of a happy man. But it may be also the way to a
|
||
greater life because it leads to not cheating.
|
||
Many, in fact, feign love of life to evade love itself. They try
|
||
their skill at enjoyment and at “indulging in experiences.” But this
|
||
is illusory. It requires a rare vocation to be a sensualist. The life of
|
||
a man is fulfilled without the aid of his mind, with its backward
|
||
and forward movements, at one and the same time its solitude and
|
||
its presences. To see these men of Belcourt working, protecting
|
||
their wives and children, and often without a reproach, I think one
|
||
can feel a secret shame. To be sure, I have no illusions about it.
|
||
There is not much love in the lives I am speaking of. I ought to say
|
||
that not much remains. But at least they have evaded nothing.
|
||
There are words I have never really understood, such as “sin.” Yet
|
||
I believe these men have never sinned against life. For if there is a
|
||
sin against life, it consists perhaps not so much in despairing of life
|
||
as in hoping for another life and in eluding the implacable
|
||
grandeur of this life. These men have not cheated. Gods of summer
|
||
they were at twenty by their enthusiasm for life, and they still are,
|
||
deprived of all hope. I have seen two of them die. They were full
|
||
of horror, but silent. It is better thus. From Pandora’s box, where
|
||
all the ills of humanity swarmed, the Greeks drew out hope after
|
||
all the others, as the most dreadful of all. I know no more stirring
|
||
symbol; for, contrary to the general belief, hope equals resignation.
|
||
And to live is not to resign oneself. This, at least, is the bitter
|
||
lesson of Algerian summers. But already the season is wavering
|
||
and summer totters. The first September rains, after such violence
|
||
and hardening, are like the liberated earth’s first tears, as if for a
|
||
few days this country tried its hand at tenderness. Yet at the same
|
||
period the carob trees cover all of Algeria with a scent of love. In
|
||
the evening or after the rain, the whole earth, its womb moist with
|
||
a seed redolent of bitter almond, rests after having given herself to
|
||
the sun all summer long. And again that scent hallows the union of
|
||
man and earth and awakens in us the only really virile love in this
|
||
world: ephemeral and noble.
|
||
(1936)
|
||
The Minotaur or The Stop In Oran
|
||
for
|
||
PIERRE GALINDO
|
||
This essay dates from 1939. The reader will have to bear this in
|
||
mind to judge of the present-day Oran. Impassioned protests from
|
||
that beautiful city assure me, as a matter of fact, that all the
|
||
imperfections have been (or will be) remedied. On the other hand,
|
||
the beauties extolled in this essay have been jealously respected.
|
||
Happy and realistic city, Oran has no further need of writers: she is
|
||
awaiting tourists.
|
||
(1953)
|
||
There are no more deserts. There are no more islands. Yet there
|
||
is a need for them. In order to understand the world, one has to turn
|
||
away from it on occasion; in order to serve men better, one has to
|
||
hold them at a distance for a time. But where can one find the
|
||
solitude necessary to vigor, the deep breath in which the mind
|
||
collects itself and courage gauges its strength? There remain big
|
||
cities. Simply, certain conditions are required.
|
||
The cities Europe offers us are too full of the din of the past. A
|
||
practiced ear can make out the flapping of wings, a fluttering of
|
||
souls. The giddy whirl of centuries, of revolutions, of fame can be
|
||
felt there. There one cannot forget that the Occident was forged in
|
||
a series of uproars. All that does not make for enough silence.
|
||
Paris is often a desert for the heart, but at certain moments
|
||
from the heights of Pere-Lachaise there blows a revolutionary
|
||
wind that suddenly fills that desert with flags and fallen glories. So
|
||
it is with certain Spanish towns, with Florence or with Prague.
|
||
Salzburg would be peaceful without Mozart. But from time to time
|
||
there rings out over the Salzach the great proud cry of Don Juan as
|
||
he plunges toward hell. Vienna seems more silent; she is a
|
||
youngster among cities. Her stones are no older than three
|
||
centuries and their youth is ignorant of melancholy. But Vienna
|
||
stands at a crossroads of history. Around her echoes the clash of
|
||
empires. Certain evenings when the sky is suffused with blood, the
|
||
stone horses on the Ring monuments seem to take wing. In that
|
||
fleeting moment when everything is reminiscent of power and
|
||
history, can he distinctly heard, under the charge of the Polish
|
||
squadrons, the crashing fall of the Ottoman Empire. That does not
|
||
make for enough silence either.
|
||
To be sure, it is just that solitude amid others that men come
|
||
looking for in European cities. At least, men with a purpose in life.
|
||
There they can choose their company, take it or leave it. How
|
||
many minds have been tempered in the trip between their hotel
|
||
room and the old stones of the Ile Saint Louis! It is true that others
|
||
have died there of isolation. As for the first, at any rate, there they
|
||
found their reasons for growing and asserting themselves. They
|
||
were alone and they weren’t alone. Centuries of history and
|
||
beauty, the ardent testimony of a thousand lives of the past
|
||
accompanied them along the Seine and spoke to them both of
|
||
traditions and of conquests. But their youth urged them to invite
|
||
such company. There comes a time, there come periods, when it is
|
||
unwelcome. “It’s between us two!” exclaims Rasti-gnac, facing the
|
||
vast mustiness of Paris. Two, yes, but that is still too many!
|
||
The desert itself has assumed significance; it has been glutted
|
||
with poetry. For all the world’s sorrows it is a hallowed spot. But
|
||
at certain moments the heart wants nothing so much as spots
|
||
devoid of poetry. Descartes, planning to meditate, chose his desert:
|
||
the most mercantile city of his era. There he found his solitude and
|
||
the occasion for perhaps the greatest of our virile poems: “The first
|
||
[precept] was never to accept anything as true unless I knew it to
|
||
be obviously so.” It is possible to have less ambition and the same
|
||
nostalgia. But during the last three centuries Amsterdam has
|
||
spawned museums. In order to flee poetry and yet recapture the
|
||
peace of stones, other deserts are needed, other spots without soul
|
||
and without reprieve. Oran is one of these.
|
||
The Street
|
||
I have often heard the people of Oran complain: “There is no
|
||
interesting circle.” No, indeed! You wouldn’t want one! A few
|
||
right-thinking people tried to introduce the customs of another
|
||
world into this desert, faithful to the principle that it is impossible
|
||
to advance art or ideas without grouping together.[34] The result is
|
||
such that the only instructive circles remain those of poker-players,
|
||
boxing enthusiasts, bowlers, and the local associations. There at
|
||
least the unsophisticated prevails. After all, there exists a certain
|
||
nobility that does not lend itself to the lofty. It is sterile by nature.
|
||
And those who want to find it leave the “circles” and go out into
|
||
the street.
|
||
The streets of Oran are doomed to dust, pebbles, and heat. If it
|
||
rains, there is a deluge and a sea of mud. But rain or shine, the
|
||
shops have the same extravagant and absurd look. All the bad taste
|
||
of Europe and the Orient has managed to converge in them. One
|
||
finds, helter-skelter, marble greyhounds, ballerinas with swans,
|
||
versions of Diana the huntress in green galalith, discus-throwers
|
||
and reapers, everything that is used for birthday and wedding gifts,
|
||
the whole race of painful figurines constantly called forth by a
|
||
commercial and playful genie on our mantelpieces. But such
|
||
perseverance in bad taste takes on a baroque aspect that makes one
|
||
forgive all. Here, presented in a casket of dust, are the contents of a
|
||
show window: frightful plaster models of deformed feet, a group
|
||
of Rembrandt drawings “sacrificed at 150 francs each,” practical
|
||
jokes, tricolored wallets, an eighteenth-century pastel, a
|
||
mechanical donkey made of plush, bottles of Provence water for
|
||
preserving green olives, and a wretched wooden virgin with an
|
||
indecent smile. (So that no one can go away ignorant, the
|
||
“management” has propped at its base a card saying: “Wooden
|
||
Virgin.”) There can be found in Oran:
|
||
1) Cafes with filter-glazed counters sprinkled with the legs and
|
||
wings of flies, the proprietor always smiling despite his always
|
||
empty cafe. A small black coffee used to cost twelve sous and a
|
||
large one eighteen.
|
||
2) Photographers’ studios where there has been no progress in
|
||
technique since the invention of sensitized paper. They exhibit a
|
||
strange fauna impossible to encounter in the streets, from the
|
||
pseudo-sailor leaning on a console table to the marriageable girl,
|
||
badly dressed and arms dangling, standing in front of a sylvan
|
||
background. It is possible to assume that these are not portraits
|
||
from life: they are creations.
|
||
3) An edifying abundance of funeral establishments. It is not
|
||
that people die more in Oran than elsewhere, but I fancy merely
|
||
that more is made of it.
|
||
The attractive naivete of this nation of merchants is displayed
|
||
even in their advertising. I read, in the handbill of an Oran movie
|
||
theater, the advertisement for a third-rate film. I note the adjectives
|
||
“sumptuous,” splendid, extraordinary, amazing, staggering, and
|
||
“tremendous.” At the end the management informs the public of
|
||
the considerable sacrifices it has undertaken to be able to present
|
||
this startling “realization.” Nevertheless, the price of tickets will
|
||
not be increased.
|
||
It would be wrong to assume that this is merely a manifestation
|
||
of that love of exaggeration characteristic of the south. Rather, the
|
||
authors of this marvelous handbill are revealing their sense of
|
||
psychology. It is essential to overcome the indifference and
|
||
profound apathy felt in this country the moment there is any
|
||
question of choosing between two shows, two careers, and, often,
|
||
even two women. People make up their minds only when forced to
|
||
do so. And advertising is well aware of this. It will assume
|
||
American proportions, having the same reasons, both here and
|
||
there, for getting desperate.
|
||
The streets of Oran inform us as to the two essential pleasures
|
||
of the local youth: getting one’s shoes shined and displaying those
|
||
same shoes on the boulevard. In order to have a clear idea of the
|
||
first of these delights, one has to entrust one’s shoes, at ten o’clock
|
||
on a Sunday morning, to the shoe-shiners in Boulevard Gal-lieni.
|
||
Perched on high armchairs, one can enjoy that peculiar satisfaction
|
||
produced, even upon a rank outsider, by the sight of men in love
|
||
with their job, as the shoe-shiners of Oran obviously are.
|
||
Everything is worked over in detail. Several brushes, three kinds of
|
||
cloths, the polish mixed with gasoline. One might think the
|
||
operation is finished when a perfect shine comes to life under the
|
||
soft brush. But the same insistent hand covers the glossy surface
|
||
again with polish, rubs it, dulls it, makes the cream penetrate the
|
||
heart of the leather, and then brings forth, under the same brush, a
|
||
double and really definitive gloss sprung from the depths of the
|
||
leather. The wonders achieved in this way are then exhibited to the
|
||
connoisseurs. In order to appreciate such pleasures of the
|
||
boulevard, you ought to see the masquerade of youth taking place
|
||
every evening on the main arteries of the city. Between the ages of
|
||
sixteen and twenty the young people of Oran “Society” borrow
|
||
their models of elegance from American films and put on their
|
||
fancy dress before going out to dinner. With wavy, oiled hair
|
||
protruding from under a felt hat slanted over the left ear and
|
||
peaked over the right eye, the neck encircled by a collar big
|
||
enough to accommodate the straggling hair, the microscopic knot
|
||
of the necktie kept in place by a regulation pin, with thigh-length
|
||
coat and waist close to the hips, with light-colored and noticeably
|
||
short trousers, with dazzlingly shiny triple-soled shoes, every
|
||
evening those youths make the sidewalks ring with their metal-
|
||
tipped soles. In all things they are bent on imitating the bearing,
|
||
forthrightness, and superiority of Mr. Clark Gable. For this reason
|
||
the local carpers commonly nickname those youths, by favor of a
|
||
casual pronunciation, “Clarques.”
|
||
At any rate, the main boulevards of Oran are invaded late in the
|
||
afternoon by an army of attractive adolescents who go to the
|
||
greatest trouble to look like a bad lot. Inasmuch as the girls of Oran
|
||
feel traditionally engaged to these softhearted gangsters, they
|
||
likewise flaunt the make-up and elegance of popular American
|
||
actresses. Consequently, the same wits call them “Marlenes.” Thus
|
||
on the evening boulevards when the sound of birds rises skyward
|
||
from the palm trees, dozens of Clarques and Marlenes meet, eye
|
||
and size up one another, happy to be alive and to cut a figure,
|
||
indulging for an hour in the intoxication of perfect existences.
|
||
There can then be witnessed, the jealous say, the meetings of the
|
||
American Commission. But in these words lies the bitterness of
|
||
those over thirty who have no connection with such diversions.
|
||
They fail to appreciate those daily congresses of youth and
|
||
romance. These are, in truth, the parliaments of birds that are met
|
||
in Hindu literature. But no one on the boulevards of Oran debates
|
||
the problem of being or worries about the way to perfection. There
|
||
remains nothing but flappings of wings, plumed struttings,
|
||
coquettish and victorious graces, a great burst of carefree song that
|
||
disappears with the night.
|
||
From here I can hear Klestakov: “I shall soon have to be
|
||
concerned with something lofty.” Alas, he is quite capable of it! If
|
||
he were urged, he would people this desert within a few years. But
|
||
for the moment a somewhat secret soul must liberate itself in this
|
||
facile city with its parade of painted girls unable, nevertheless, to
|
||
simulate emotion, feigning coyness so badly that the pretense is
|
||
immediately obvious. Be concerned with something lofty! Just see:
|
||
Santa-Cruz cut out of the rock, the mountains, the flat sea, the
|
||
violent wind and the sun, the great cranes of the harbor, the trains,
|
||
the hangars, the quays, and the huge ramps climbing up the city’s
|
||
rock, and in the city itself these diversions and this boredom, this
|
||
hubbub and this solitude. Perhaps, indeed, all this is not
|
||
sufficiently lofty. But the great value of such overpopulated islands
|
||
is that in them the heart strips bare. Silence is no longer possible
|
||
except in noisy cities. From Amsterdam Descartes writes to the
|
||
aged Guez de Balzac: “I go out walking every day amid the
|
||
confusion of a great crowd, with as much freedom and tranquillity
|
||
as you could do on your garden paths.” [35]
|
||
The Desert in Oran
|
||
Obliged to live facing a wonderful landscape, the people of
|
||
Oran have overcome this fearful ordeal by covering their city with
|
||
very ugly constructions. One expects to find a city open to the sea,
|
||
washed and refreshed by the evening breeze. And aside from the
|
||
Spanish quarter,[36] one finds a walled town that turns its back to
|
||
the sea, that has been built up by turning back on itself like a snail.
|
||
Oran is a great circular yellow wall covered over with a leaden
|
||
sky. In the beginning you wander in the labyrinth, seeking the sea
|
||
like the sign of Ariadne. But you turn round and round in pale and
|
||
oppressive streets, and eventually the Minotaur devours the people
|
||
of Oran: the Minotaur is boredom. For some time the citizens of
|
||
Oran have given up wandering. They have accepted being eaten.
|
||
It is impossible to know what stone is without coming to Oran.
|
||
In that dustiest of cities, the pebble is king. It is so much
|
||
appreciated that shopkeepers exhibit it in their show windows to
|
||
hold papers in place or even for mere display. Piles of them are set
|
||
up along the streets, doubtless for the eyes’ delight, since a year
|
||
later the pile is still there. Whatever elsewhere derives its poetry
|
||
from the vegetable kingdom here takes on a stone face. The
|
||
hundred or so trees that can be found in the business section have
|
||
been carefully covered with dust. They are petrified plants whose
|
||
branches give off an acrid, dusty smell. In Algiers the Arab
|
||
cemeteries have a well-known mellowness. In Oran, above the
|
||
Ras-el-Ain ravine, facing the sea this time, flat against the blue
|
||
sky, are fields of chalky, friable pebbles in which the sun blinds
|
||
with its fires. Amid these bare bones of the earth a purple
|
||
geranium, from time to time, contributes its life and fresh blood to
|
||
the landscape. The whole city has solidified in a stony matrix. Seen
|
||
from Les Planteurs, the depth of the cliffs surrounding it is so great
|
||
that the landscape becomes unreal, so mineral it is. Man is
|
||
outlawed from it. So much heavy beauty seems to come from
|
||
another world.
|
||
If the desert can be defined as a soulless place where the sky
|
||
alone is king, then Oran is awaiting her prophets. All around and
|
||
above the city the brutal nature of Africa is indeed clad in her
|
||
burning charms. She bursts the unfortunate stage setting with
|
||
which she is covered; she shrieks forth between all the houses and
|
||
over all the roofs. If one climbs one of the roads up the mountain
|
||
of Santa-Cruz, the first thing to be visible is the scattered colored
|
||
cubes of Oran. But a little higher and already the jagged cliffs that
|
||
surround the plateau crouch in the sea like red beasts. Still a little
|
||
higher and a great vortex of sun and wind sweeps over, airs out,
|
||
and obscures the untidy city scattered in disorder all over a rocky
|
||
landscape. The opposition here is between magnificent human
|
||
anarchy and the permanence of an unchanging sea. This is enough
|
||
to make a staggering scent of life rise toward the mountainside
|
||
road.
|
||
There is something implacable about the desert. The mineral
|
||
sky of Oran, her streets and trees in their coating of dust—
|
||
everything contributes to creating this dense and impassible
|
||
universe in which the heart and mind are never distracted from
|
||
themselves, nor from their sole object, which is man. I am
|
||
speaking here of difficult places of retreat. Books are written on
|
||
Florence or Athens. Those cities have formed so many European
|
||
minds that they must have a meaning. They have the means of
|
||
moving to tears or of uplifting. They quiet a certain spiritual
|
||
hunger whose bread is memory. But can one be moved by a city
|
||
where nothing attracts the mind, where the very ugliness is
|
||
anonymous, where the past is reduced to nothing? Emptiness,
|
||
boredom, an indifferent sky, what are the charms of such places?
|
||
Doubtless solitude and, perhaps, the human creature.
|
||
For a certain race of men, wherever the human creature is
|
||
beautiful is a bitter native land. Oran is one of its thousand capitals.
|
||
Sports
|
||
The Central Sporting Club, on rue du Fondouk in Oran, is
|
||
giving an evening of boxing which it insists will be appreciated by
|
||
real enthusiasts. Interpreted, this means that the boxers on the bill
|
||
are far from being stars, that some of them are entering the ring for
|
||
the first time, and that consequently you can count, if not on the
|
||
skill, at least on the courage of the opponents. A native having
|
||
thrilled me with the firm promise that “blood would flow,” I find
|
||
myself that evening among the real enthusiasts.
|
||
Apparently the latter never insist on comfort. To be sure, a ring
|
||
has been set up at the back of a sort of whitewashed garage,
|
||
covered with corrugated iron and violently lighted. Folding chairs
|
||
have been lined up in a square around the ropes. These are the
|
||
“honor rings.” Most of the length of the hall has been filled with
|
||
seats, and behind them opens a large free space called “lounge” by
|
||
reason of the fact that not one of the five hundred persons in it
|
||
could take out a handkerchief without causing serious accidents. In
|
||
this rectangular box live and breathe some thousand men and two
|
||
or three women—the kind who, according to my neighbor, always
|
||
insist on “attracting attention.” Everybody is sweating fiercely.
|
||
While waiting for the fights of the “young hopefuls” a gigantic
|
||
phonograph grinds out a Tino Rossi record. This is the sentimental
|
||
song before the murder.
|
||
The patience of a true enthusiast is unlimited. The fight
|
||
announced for nine o’clock has not even begun at nine thirty and
|
||
no one has protested. The spring weather is warm and the smell of
|
||
a humanity in shirt sleeves is exciting. Lively discussion goes on
|
||
among the periodic explosions of lemon-soda corks and the tireless
|
||
lament of the Corsican singer. A few late arrivals are wedged into
|
||
the audience when a spotlight throws a blinding light onto the ring.
|
||
The fights of the young hopefuls begin.
|
||
The young hopefuls, or beginners, who are fighting for the fun
|
||
of it, are always eager to prove this by massacring each other at the
|
||
earliest opportunity, in defiance of technique. They were never
|
||
able to last more than three rounds. The hero of the evening in this
|
||
regard is young “Kid Airplane,” who in regular life sells lottery
|
||
tickets on cafe terraces. His opponent, indeed, hurtled awkwardly
|
||
out of the ring at the beginning of the second round after contact
|
||
with a fist wielded like a propeller.
|
||
The crowd got somewhat excited, but this is still an act of
|
||
courtesy. Gravely it breathes in the hallowed air of the
|
||
embrocation. It watches these series of slow rites and unregulated
|
||
sacrifices, made even more authentic by the propitiatory designs,
|
||
on the white wall, of the fighters’ shadows. These are the
|
||
deliberate ceremonial prologues of a savage religion. The trance
|
||
will not come until later.
|
||
And it so happens that the loudspeaker announces Amar, “the
|
||
tough Oranese who has never disarmed,” against Perez, “the
|
||
slugger from Algiers.” An uninitiate would misinterpret the yelling
|
||
that greets the introduction of the boxers in the ring. He would
|
||
imagine some sensational combat in which the boxers were to
|
||
settle a personal quarrel known to the public. To tell the truth, it is
|
||
a quarrel they are going to settle. But it is the one that for the past
|
||
hundred years has mortally separated Algiers and Oran. Back in
|
||
history, these two North African cities would have already bled
|
||
each other white as Pisa and Florence did in happier times. Their
|
||
rivalry is all the stronger just because it probably has no basis.
|
||
Having every reason to like each other, they loathe each other
|
||
proportionately. The Oranese accuse the citizens of Algiers of
|
||
“sham.” The people of Algiers imply that the Oranese are rustic.
|
||
These are bloodier insults than they might seem because they are
|
||
metaphysical. And unable to lay siege to each other, Oran and
|
||
Algiers meet, compete, and insult each other on the field of sports,
|
||
statistics, and public works.
|
||
Thus a page of history is unfolding in the ring. And the tough
|
||
Oranese, backed by a thousand yelling voices, is defending against
|
||
Perez a way of life and the pride of a province. Truth forces me to
|
||
admit that Amar is not conducting his discussion well. His
|
||
argument has a flaw: he lacks reach. The slugger from Algiers, on
|
||
the contrary, has the required reach in his argument. It lands
|
||
persuasively between his contradictor’s eyes. The Oranese bleeds
|
||
magnificently amid the vociferations of a wild audience. Despite
|
||
the repeated encouragements of the gallery and of my neighbor,
|
||
despite the dauntless shouts of “Kill him!”, “Floor him!”, the
|
||
insidious “Below the belt,”
|
||
“Oh, the referee missed that one!”, the optimistic “He’s
|
||
pooped,” “He can’t take any more,” nevertheless the man from
|
||
Algiers is proclaimed the winner on points amid interminable
|
||
catcalls. My neighbor, who is inclined to talk of sportsmanship,
|
||
applauds ostensibly, while slipping to me in a voice made faint by
|
||
so many shouts: “So that he won’t be able to say back there that
|
||
we of Oran are savages.”
|
||
But throughout the audience, fights not included on the
|
||
program have already broken out. Chairs are brandished, the police
|
||
clear a path, excitement is at its height. In order to calm these good
|
||
people and contribute to the return of silence, the “management,”
|
||
without losing a moment, commissions the loudspeaker to boom
|
||
out “Sambre-et-Meuse.” For a few minutes the audience has a
|
||
really warlike look. Confused clusters of com-batants and
|
||
voluntary referees sway in the grip of policemen; the gallery exults
|
||
and calls for the rest of the program with wild cries, cock-a-
|
||
doodle-doo’s, and mocking catcalls drowned in the irresistible
|
||
flood from the military band.
|
||
But the announcement or the big fight is enough to restore
|
||
calm. This takes place suddenly, without flourishes, just as actors
|
||
leave the stage once the play is finished. With the greatest
|
||
unconcern, hats are dusted off, chairs are put back in place, and
|
||
without transition all faces assume the kindly expression of the
|
||
respectable member of the audience who has paid for his ticket to a
|
||
family concert.
|
||
The last fight pits a French champion of the Navy against an
|
||
Oran boxer. This time the difference in reach is to the advantage of
|
||
the latter. But his superiorities, during the first rounds, do not stir
|
||
the crowd. They are sleeping off the effects of their first
|
||
excitement; they are sobering up. They are still short of breath. If
|
||
they applaud, there is no passion in it. They hiss without animosity.
|
||
The audience is divided into two camps, as is appropriate in the
|
||
interest of fairness. But each individual’s choice obeys that
|
||
indifference that follows on great expenditures of energy. If the
|
||
Frenchman holds his own, if the Oranese forgets that one doesn’t
|
||
lead with the head, the boxer is bent under a volley of hisses, but
|
||
immediately pulled upright again by a burst of applause. Not until
|
||
the seventh round does sport rise to the surface again, at the same
|
||
time that the real enthusiasts begin to emerge from their fatigue.
|
||
The Frenchman, to tell the truth, has touched the mat and, eager to
|
||
win back points, has hurled himself on his opponent. “What did I
|
||
tell you?” said my neighbor; “it’s going to be a fight to the finish.”
|
||
Indeed, it is a fight to the finish. Covered with sweat under the
|
||
pitiless light, both boxers open their guard, close their eyes as they
|
||
hit, shove with shoulders and knees, swap their blood, and snort
|
||
with rage. As one man, the audience has stood up and punctuates
|
||
the efforts of its two heroes. It receives the blows, returns them,
|
||
echoes them in a thousand hollow, panting voices. The same ones
|
||
who had chosen their favorite in indifference cling to their choice
|
||
through obstinacy and defend it passionately. Every ten seconds a
|
||
shout from my neighbor pierces my right ear: “Go to it, gob; come
|
||
on, Navy!” while another man in front of us shouts to the Oranese:
|
||
“Anda! hombre!” The man and the gob go to it, and together with
|
||
them, in this temple of whitewash, iron, and cement, an audience
|
||
completely given over to gods with cauliflower ears. Every blow
|
||
that gives a dull sound on the shining pectorals echoes in vast
|
||
vibrations in the very body of the crowd, which, with the boxers, is
|
||
making its last effort.
|
||
In such an atmosphere a draw is badly received. Indeed, it runs
|
||
counter to a quite Manichean tendency in the audience. There is
|
||
good and there is evil, the winner and the loser. One must be either
|
||
right or wrong. The conclusion of this impeccable logic is
|
||
immediately provided by two thousand energetic lungs accusing
|
||
the judges of being sold, or bought. But the gob has walked over
|
||
and embraced his rival in the ring, drinking in his fraternal sweat.
|
||
This is enough to make the audience, reversing its view, burst out
|
||
in sudden applause. My neighbor is right: they are not savages.
|
||
The crowd pouring out, under a sky full of silence and stars,
|
||
has just fought the most exhausting fight. It keeps quiet and
|
||
disappears furtively, without any energy left for post mortems.
|
||
There is good and there is evil; that religion is merciless. The band
|
||
of faithful is now no more than a group of black-and-white
|
||
shadows disappearing into the night. For force and violence are
|
||
solitary gods. They contribute nothing to memory. On the contrary,
|
||
they distribute their miracles by the handful in the present. They
|
||
are made for this race without past which celebrates its
|
||
communions around the prize ring. These are rather difficult rites
|
||
but ones that simplify everything. Good and evil, winner and loser.
|
||
At Corinth two temples stood side by side, the temple of Violence
|
||
and the temple of Necessity.
|
||
Monuments
|
||
For many reasons due as much to economics as to metaphysics,
|
||
it may be said that the Oranese style, if there is one, forcefully and
|
||
clearly appears in the extraordinary edifice called the Maison du
|
||
Colon. Oran hardly lacks monuments. The city has its quota of
|
||
imperial marshals, ministers, and local benefactors. They are found
|
||
on dusty little squares, resigned to rain and sun, they too converted
|
||
to stone and boredom. But, in any case, they represent
|
||
contributions from the outside. In that happy barbary they are the
|
||
regrettable marks of civilization.
|
||
Oran, on the other hand, has raised up her altars and rostra to
|
||
her own honor. In the very heart of the mercantile city, having to
|
||
construct a common home for the innumerable agricultural
|
||
organizations that keep this country alive, the people of Oran
|
||
conceived the idea of building solidly a convincing image of their
|
||
virtues: the Maison du Colon. To judge from the edifice, those
|
||
virtues are three in number: boldness in taste, love of violence, and
|
||
a feeling for historical syntheses. Egypt, Byzantium, and Munich
|
||
collaborated in the delicate construction of a piece of pastry in the
|
||
shape of a bowl upside down. Multicolored stones, most vigorous
|
||
in effect, have been brought in to outline the roof. These mosaics
|
||
are so exuberantly persuasive that at first you see nothing but an
|
||
amorphous effulgence. But with a closer view and your attention
|
||
called to it, you discover that they have a meaning: a graceful
|
||
colonist, wearing a bow tie and white pith helmet, is receiving the
|
||
homage of a procession of slaves dressed in classical style.[37] The
|
||
edifice and its colored illustrations have been set down in the
|
||
middle of a square in the to-and-fro of the little two-car trams
|
||
whose filth is one of the charms of the city.
|
||
Oran greatly cherishes also the two lions of its Place d’Armes,
|
||
or parade ground. Since 1888 they have been sitting in state on
|
||
opposite sides of the municipal stairs. Their author was named (
|
||
ain. They have majesty and a stubby torso. It is said that at night
|
||
they get down from their pedestal one after the other, silently pace
|
||
around the dark square, and on occasion uninate at length under the
|
||
big, dusty ficus trees. These, of course, are rumors to which the
|
||
people of Oran lend an indulgent ear. But it is unlikely.
|
||
Despite a certain amount of research, I have not been able to
|
||
get interested in Cain. I merely learned that he had the reputation
|
||
of being a skillful animal-sculptor. Yet I often think of him. This is
|
||
an intellectual bent that comes naturally in Oran. Here is a
|
||
sonorously named artist who left an unimportant work here.
|
||
Several hundred thousand people are familiar with the easygoing
|
||
beasts he put in front of a pretentious town hall. This is one way of
|
||
succeeding in art. To be sure, these two lions, like thousands of
|
||
works of the same type, are proof of something else than talent.
|
||
Others have created “The Night Watch,” “Saint Francis Receiving
|
||
the Stigmata,” “David,” or the Pharsalian bas-relief called “The
|
||
Glorification of the Flower.” Cain, on the other hand, set up two
|
||
hilarious snouts on the square of a mercantile province overseas.
|
||
But the David will go down one day with Florence and the lions
|
||
will perhaps be saved from the catastrophe. Let me repeat, they are
|
||
proof of something else.
|
||
Can one state this idea clearly? In this work there are
|
||
insignificance and solidity. Spirit counts for nothing and matter for
|
||
a great deal. Mediocrity insists upon lasting by all means,
|
||
including bronze. It is refused a right to eternity, and every day it
|
||
takes that right. Is it not eternity itself? In any event, such
|
||
perseverance is capable of stirring, and it involves its lesson, that
|
||
of all the monuments of Oran, and of Oran herself. An hour a day,
|
||
every so often, it forces you to pay attention to something that has
|
||
no importance. The mind profits from such recurrences. In a sense
|
||
this is its hygiene, and since it absolutely needs its moments of
|
||
humility, it seems to me that this chance to indulge in stupidity is
|
||
better than others. Everything that is ephemeral wants to last. Let
|
||
us say that everything wants to last. Human productions mean
|
||
nothing else, and in this regard Cain’s lions have the same chances
|
||
as the ruins of Angkor. This disposes one toward modesty.
|
||
There are other Oranese monuments. Or at least they deserve
|
||
this name because they, too, stand for their city, and perhaps in a
|
||
more significant way. They are the public works at present
|
||
covering the coast for some ten kilometers. Apparently it is a
|
||
matter of transforming the most luminous of bays into a gigantic
|
||
harbor. In reality it is one more chance for man to come to grips
|
||
with stone.
|
||
In the paintings of certain Flemish masters a theme of
|
||
strikingly general application recurs insistently: the building of the
|
||
Tower of Babel. Vast landscapes, rocks climbing up to heaven,
|
||
steep slopes teeming with workmen, animals, ladders, strange
|
||
machines, cords, pulleys. Man, moreover, is there only to give
|
||
scale to the inhuman scope of the construction. This is what the
|
||
Oran coast makes one think of, west of the city.
|
||
Clinging to vast slopes, rails, dump-cars, cranes, tiny trains ...
|
||
Under a broiling sun, toy-like locomotives round huge blocks of
|
||
stone amid whistles, dust, and smoke. Day and night a nation of
|
||
ants bustles about on the smoking carcass of the mountain.
|
||
Clinging all up and down a single cord against the side of the cliff,
|
||
dozens of men, their bellies pushing against the handles of
|
||
automatic drills, vibrate in empty space all day long and break off
|
||
whole masses of rock that hurtle down in dust and rumbling.
|
||
Farther on, dump-carts tip their loads over the slopes; and the
|
||
rocks, suddenly poured seaward, bound and roll into the water,
|
||
each large lump followed by a scattering of lighter stones. At
|
||
regular intervals, at dead of night or in broad daylight, detonations
|
||
shake the whole mountain and stir up the sea itself.
|
||
Man, in this vast construction field, makes a frontal attack on
|
||
stone. And if one could forget, for a moment at least, the harsh
|
||
slavery that makes this work possible, one would have to admire.
|
||
These stones, torn from the mountain, serve man in his plans. They
|
||
pile up under the first waves, gradually emerge, and finally take
|
||
their place to form a jetty, soon covered with men and machines
|
||
which advance, day after day, toward the open sea. Without
|
||
stopping, huge steel jaws bite into the cliff’s belly, turn round, and
|
||
disgorge into the water their overflowing gravel. As the coastal
|
||
cliff is lowered, the whole coast encroaches irresistibly on the sea.
|
||
Of course, destroying stone is not possible. It is merely moved
|
||
from one place to another. In any case, it will last longer than the
|
||
men who use it. For the moment, it satisfies their will to action.
|
||
That in itself is probably useless. But moving things about is the
|
||
work of men; one must choose doing that or nothing.[38] Obviously
|
||
the people of Oran have chosen. In front of that indifferent bay, for
|
||
many years more they will pile up stones along the coast. In a
|
||
hundred years—tomorrow, in other words—they will have to
|
||
begin again. But today these heaps of rocks testify for the men in
|
||
masks of dust and sweat who move about among them. The true
|
||
monuments of Oran are still her stones.
|
||
Ariadne’s Stone
|
||
It seems that the people of Oran are like that friend of Flaubert
|
||
who, on the point of death, casting a last glance at this
|
||
irreplaceable earth, exclaimed: “Close the window; it’s too
|
||
beautiful.” They have closed the window, they have walled
|
||
themselves in, they have cast out the landscape. But Flaubert’s
|
||
friend, Le Poittevin, died, and after him days continued to be added
|
||
to days. Likewise, beyond the yellow walls of Oran, land and sea
|
||
continue their indifferent dialogue. That permanence in the world
|
||
has always had contrary charms for man. It drives him to despair
|
||
and excites him. The world never says but one thing; first it
|
||
interests, then it bores. But eventually it wins out by dint of
|
||
obstinacy. It is always right.
|
||
Already, at the very gates of Oran, nature raises its voice. In
|
||
the direction of Canastel there are vast wastelands covered with
|
||
fragrant brush. There sun and wind speak only of solitude. Above
|
||
Oran there is the mountain of Santa-Cruz, the plateau and the
|
||
myriad ravines leading to it. Roads, once carriageable, cling to the
|
||
slopes overhanging the sea. In the month of January some are
|
||
covered with flowers. Daisies and buttercups turn them into
|
||
sumptuous paths, embroidered in yellow and white. About Sant-
|
||
Cruzz everything has been said. But if I were to speak of it, I
|
||
should forget the sacred processions that climb the rugged hill on
|
||
feast days, in order to recall other pilgrimages. Solitary, they walk
|
||
in the red stone, rise above the motionless bay, and come to
|
||
dedicate to nakedness a luminous, perfect hour.
|
||
Oran has also its deserts of sand: its beaches. Those
|
||
encountered near the gates are deserted only in winter and spring.
|
||
Then they are plateaus covered with asphodels, peopled with bare
|
||
little cottages among the flowers. The sea rumbles a bit, down
|
||
below. Yet already the sun, the faint breeze, the whiteness of the
|
||
asphodels, the sharp blue of the sky, everything makes one fancy
|
||
summer—the golden youth then covering the beach, the long hours
|
||
on the sand and the sudden softness of evening. Each year on these
|
||
shores there is a new harvest of girls in flower. Apparently they
|
||
have but one season. The following year, other cordial blossoms
|
||
take their place, which, the summer before, were still little girls
|
||
with bodies as hard as buds. At eleven a.m., coming down from the
|
||
plateau, all that young flesh, lightly clothed in motley materials,
|
||
breaks on the sand like a multicolored wave.
|
||
One has to go farther (strangely close, however, to that spot
|
||
where two hundred thousand men are laboring) to discover a still
|
||
virgin landscape: long, deserted dunes where the passage of men
|
||
has left no other trace than a worm-eaten hut. From time to time an
|
||
Arab shepherd drives along the top of the dunes the black and
|
||
beige spots of his flock of goats. On the beaches of the Oran
|
||
country every summer morning seems to be the first in the world.
|
||
Each twilight seems to be the last, solemn agony, announced at
|
||
sunset by a final glow that darkens every hue. The sea is
|
||
ultramarine, the road the color of clotted blood, the beach yellow.
|
||
Everything disappears with the green sun; an hour later the dunes
|
||
are bathed in moonlight. Then there are incomparable nights under
|
||
a rain of stars. Occasionally storms sweep over them, and the
|
||
lightning flashes flow along the dunes, whiten the sky, and give the
|
||
sand and one’s eyes orange-colored glints.
|
||
But this cannot be shared. One has to have lived it. So much
|
||
solitude and nobility give these places an unforgettable aspect. In
|
||
the warm moment before daybreak, after confronting the first
|
||
bitter, black waves, a new creature breasts night’s heavy,
|
||
enveloping water. The memory of those joys does not make me
|
||
regret them, and thus I recognize that they were good. After so
|
||
many years they still last, somewhere in this heart which finds
|
||
unswerving loyalty so difficult. And I know that today, if I were to
|
||
go to the deserted dune, the same sky would pour down on me its
|
||
cargo of breezes and stars. These are lands of innocence.
|
||
But innocence needs sand and stones. And man has forgotten
|
||
how to live among them. At least it seems so, for he has taken
|
||
refuge in this extraordinary city where boredom sleeps.
|
||
Nevertheless, that very confrontation constitutes the value of Oran.
|
||
The capital of boredom, besieged by innocence and beauty, it is
|
||
surrounded by an army in which every stone is a soldier. In the
|
||
city, and at certain hours, however, what a temptation to go over to
|
||
the enemy! What a temptation to identify oneself with those
|
||
stones, to melt into that burning and impassive universe that defies
|
||
history and its ferments! That is doubtless futile. But there is in
|
||
every man a profound instinct which is neither that of destruction
|
||
nor that of creation. It is merely a matter of resembling nothing. In
|
||
the shadow of the warm walls of Oran, on its dusty asphalt, that
|
||
invitation is sometimes heard. It seems that, for a time, the minds
|
||
that yield to it are never disappointed. This is the darkness of
|
||
Eurydice and the sleep of Isis. Here are the deserts where thought
|
||
will collect itself, the cool hand of evening on a troubled heart. On
|
||
this Mount of Olives, vigil is futile; the mind recalls and approves
|
||
the sleeping Apostles. Were they really wrong? They nonetheless
|
||
had their revelation.
|
||
Just think of Sakyamuni in the desert. He remained there for
|
||
years on end, squatting motionless with his eyes on heaven. The
|
||
very gods envied him that wisdom and that stone-like destiny. In
|
||
his outstretched hands the swallows had made their nest. But one
|
||
day they flew away, answering the call of distant lands. And he
|
||
who had stifled in himself desire and will, fame and suffering,
|
||
began to cry. It happens thus that flowers grow on rocks. Yes, let
|
||
us accept stone when it is necessary. That secret and that rapture
|
||
we ask of faces can also be given us by stone. To be sure, this
|
||
cannot last. But what can last, after all? The secret of faces fades
|
||
away, and there we are, cast back to the chain of desires. And if
|
||
stone can do no more for us than the human heart, at least it can do
|
||
just as much.
|
||
“Oh, to be nothing!” For thousands of years this great cry has
|
||
roused millions of men to revolt against desire and pain. Its dying
|
||
echoes have reached this far, across centuries and oceans, to the
|
||
oldest sea in the world. They still reverberate dully against the
|
||
compact cliffs of Oran. Everybody in this country follows this
|
||
advice without knowing it. Of course, it is almost futile.
|
||
Nothingness cannot be achieved any more than the absolute can.
|
||
But since we receive as favors the eternal signs brought us by roses
|
||
or by human suffering, let us not refuse either the rare invitations
|
||
to sleep that the earth addresses us. Each has as much truth as the
|
||
other.
|
||
This, perhaps, is the Ariadne’s thread of this somnambulist and
|
||
frantic city. Here one learns the virtues, provisional to be sure, of a
|
||
certain kind of boredom. In order to be spared, one must say “yes”
|
||
to the Minotaur. This is an old and fecund wisdom. Above the sea,
|
||
silent at the base of the red cliffs, it is enough to maintain a
|
||
delicate equilibrium halfway between the two massive headlands
|
||
which, on the right and left, dip into the clear water. In the puffing
|
||
of a coast-guard vessel crawling along the water far out bathed in
|
||
radiant light, is distinctly heard the muffled call of inhuman and
|
||
glittering forces: it is the Minotaur’s farewell.
|
||
It is noon; the very day is being weighed in the balance. His
|
||
rite accomplished, the traveler receives the reward of his liberation:
|
||
the little stone, dry and smooth as an asphodel, that he picks up on
|
||
the cliff. For the initiate the world is no heavier to bear than this
|
||
stone. Atlas’s task is easy; it is sufficient to choose one’s hour.
|
||
Then one realizes that for an hour, a month, a year, these shores
|
||
can indulge in freedom. They welcome pell-mell, without even
|
||
looking at them, the monk, the civil servant, or the conqueror.
|
||
There are days when I expected to meet, in the streets of Oran,
|
||
Descartes or Cesare Borgia. That did not happen. But perhaps
|
||
another will be more fortunate. A great deed, a great work, virile
|
||
meditation used to call for the solitude of sands or of the convent.
|
||
There were kept the spiritual vigils of arms. Where could they be
|
||
better celebrated now than in the emptiness of a big city
|
||
established for some time in unintellectual beauty?
|
||
Here is the little stone, smooth as an asphodel. It is at the
|
||
beginning of everything. Flowers, tears (if you insist), departures,
|
||
and struggles are for tomorrow. In the middle of the day when the
|
||
sky opens its fountains of light in the vast, sonorous space, all the
|
||
headlands of the coast look like a fleet about to set out. Those
|
||
heavy galleons of rock and light are trembling on their keels as if
|
||
they were preparing to steer for sunlit isles. O mornings in the
|
||
country of Oran! From the high plateaus the swallows plunge into
|
||
huge troughs where the air is seething. The whole coast is ready
|
||
for departure; a shiver of adventure ripples through it. Tomorrow,
|
||
perhaps, we shall leave together.
|
||
(1939)
|
||
Helen’s Exile
|
||
The mediterranean sun has something tragic about it, quite
|
||
different from the tragedy of fogs. Certain evenings at the base of
|
||
the seaside mountains, night falls over the flawless curve of a little
|
||
bay, and there rises from the silent waters a sense of anguished
|
||
fulfillment. In such spots one can understand that if the Greeks
|
||
knew despair, they always did so through beauty and its stifling
|
||
quality. In that gilded calamity, tragedy reaches its highest point.
|
||
Our time, on the other hand, has fed its despair on ugliness and
|
||
convulsions. This is why Europe would be vile, if suffering could
|
||
ever be so. We have exiled beauty; the Greeks took up arms for
|
||
her. First difference, but one that has a history. Greek thought
|
||
always took refuge behind the conception of limits. It never carried
|
||
anything to extremes, neither the sacred nor reason, because it
|
||
negated nothing, neither the sacred nor reason. It took everything
|
||
into consideration, balancing shadow with light. Our Europe, on
|
||
the other hand, off in the pursuit of totality, is the child of
|
||
disproportion. She negates beauty, as she negates whatever she
|
||
does not glorify. And, through all her diverse ways, she glorifies
|
||
but one thing, which is the future rule of reason. In her madness
|
||
she extends the eternal limits, and at that very moment dark
|
||
Erinyes fall upon her and tear her to pieces. Nemesis, the goddess
|
||
of measure and not of revenge, keeps watch. All those who
|
||
overstep the limit are pitilessly punished by her.
|
||
The Greeks, who for centuries questioned themselves as to
|
||
what is just, could understand nothing of our idea of justice. For
|
||
them equity implied a limit, whereas our whole continent is
|
||
convulsed in its search for a justice that must be total. At the dawn
|
||
of Greek thought Hera-clitus was already imagining that justice
|
||
sets limits for the physical universe itself: “The sun will not
|
||
overstep his measures; if he does, the Erinyes, the handmaids of
|
||
justice, will find him out.” 1 We who have cast the universe and
|
||
spirit out of our sphere laugh at that threat. In a drunken sky we
|
||
light up the suns we want. But nonetheless the boundaries exist,
|
||
and we know it. In our wildest aberrations we dream of an
|
||
equilibrium we have left behind, which we naively expect to find
|
||
at the end of our errors. Childish presumption which justifies the
|
||
fact that child-nations, inheriting our follies, are now directing our
|
||
history.
|
||
A fragment attributed to the same Heraclitus simply states:
|
||
“Presumption, regression of progress.” And, many centuries after
|
||
the man of Ephesus, Socrates, facing the threat of being
|
||
condemned to death, acknowledged only this one superiority in
|
||
himself: what he did not know he did not claim to know. The most
|
||
exemplary life and thought of those centuries close on a proud
|
||
confession of ignorance. Forgetting that, we have forgotten our
|
||
virility. We have preferred the power that apes greatness, first
|
||
Alexander and then the Roman conquerors whom the authors of
|
||
our schoolbooks, through some incomparable vulgarity, teach us to
|
||
admire. We, too, have conquered, moved boundaries, mastered 1
|
||
Bywater’s translation. [Translator’s note.]
|
||
heaven and earth. Our reason has driven all away. Alone at last,
|
||
we end up by ruling over a desert. What imagination could we
|
||
have left for that higher equilibrium in which nature balanced
|
||
history, beauty, virtue, and which applied the music of numbers
|
||
even to blood-tragedy? We turn our backs on nature; we are
|
||
ashamed of beauty. Our wretched tragedies have a smell of the
|
||
office clinging to them, and the blood that trickles from them is the
|
||
color of printer’s ink.
|
||
This is why it is improper to proclaim today that we are the
|
||
sons of Greece. Or else we are the renegade sons. Placing history
|
||
on the throne of God, we are progressing toward theocracy like
|
||
those whom the Greeks called Barbarians and whom they fought to
|
||
death in the waters of Salamis. In order to realize how we differ,
|
||
one must turn to him among our philosophers who is the true rival
|
||
of Plato. “Only the modern city,” Hegel dares write, “offers the
|
||
mind a field in which it can become aware of itself.” We are thus
|
||
living in the period of big cities. Deliberately, the world has been
|
||
amputated of all that constitutes its permanence: nature, the sea,
|
||
hilltops, evening meditation. Consciousness is to be found only in
|
||
the streets, because history is to be found only in the streets—this
|
||
is the edict. And consequently our most significant works show the
|
||
same bias. Landscapes are not to be found in great European
|
||
literature since Dostoevsky. History explains neither the natural
|
||
universe that existed before it nor the beauty that exists above it.
|
||
Hence it chose to be ignorant of them. Whereas Plato contained
|
||
everything—nonsense, reason, and myth—our philosophers
|
||
contain nothing but nonsense or reason because they have closed
|
||
their eyes to the rest. The mole is meditating.
|
||
It is Christianity that began substituting the tragedy of the soul
|
||
for contemplation of the world. But, at least, Christianity referred
|
||
to a spiritual nature and thereby preserved a certain fixity. With
|
||
God dead, there remains only history and power. For some time
|
||
the entire effort of our philosophers has aimed solely at replacing
|
||
the notion of human nature with that of situation, and replacing
|
||
ancient harmony with the disorderly advance of chance or reason’s
|
||
pitiless progress. Whereas the Greeks gave to will the boundaries
|
||
of reason, we have come to put the will’s impulse in the very
|
||
center of reason, which has, as a result, become deadly. For the
|
||
Greeks, values pre-existed all action, of which they definitely set
|
||
the limits. Modern philosophy places its values at the end of
|
||
action. They are not but are becoming, and we shall know them
|
||
fully only at the completion of history. With values, all limit
|
||
disappears, and since conceptions differ as to what they will be,
|
||
since all struggles, without the brake of those same values, spread
|
||
indefinitely, today’s Messianisms confront one another and their
|
||
clamors mingle in the clash of empires. Disproportion is a
|
||
conflagration, according to Heraclitus. The conflagration is
|
||
spreading; Nietzsche is outdistanced. Europe no longer
|
||
philosophizes by striking a hammer, but by shooting a cannon.
|
||
Nature is still there, however. She contrasts her calm skies and
|
||
her reasons with the madness of men. Until the atom too catches
|
||
fire and history ends in the triumph of reason and the agony of the
|
||
species. But the Greeks never said that the limit could not he
|
||
overstepped. They said it existed and that whoever dared to exceed
|
||
it was mercilessly struck down. Nothing in present history can
|
||
contradict them.
|
||
The historical spirit and the artist both want to remake the
|
||
world. But the artist, through an obligation of his nature, knows his
|
||
limits, which the historical spirit fails to recognize. This is why the
|
||
latter’s aim is tyranny whereas the former’s passion is freedom. All
|
||
those who are struggling for freedom today are ultimately fighting
|
||
for beauty. Of course, it is not a question of defending beauty for
|
||
itself. Beauty cannot do without man, and we shall not give our era
|
||
its nobility and serenity unless we follow it in its misfortune. Never
|
||
again shall we be hermits. But it is no less true that man cannot do
|
||
without beauty, and this is what our era pretends to want to
|
||
disregard. It steels itself to attain the absolute and authority; it
|
||
wants to transfigure the world before having exhausted it, to set it
|
||
to rights before having understood it. Whatever it may say, our era
|
||
is deserting this world. Ulysses can choose at Calypso’s bidding
|
||
between immortality and the land of his fathers. He chooses the
|
||
land, and death with it. Such simple nobility is foreign to us today.
|
||
Others will say that we lack humility; but, all things considered,
|
||
this word is ambiguous. Like Dostoevsky’s fools who boast of
|
||
everything, soar to heaven, and end up flaunting their shame in any
|
||
public place, we merely lack man’s pride, which is fidelity to his
|
||
limits, lucid love of his condition.
|
||
“I hate my time,” Saint-Exupery wrote shortly before his death,
|
||
for reasons not far removed from those I have spoken of. But,
|
||
however upsetting that exclamation, coming from him who loved
|
||
men for their admirable qualities, we shall not accept responsibility
|
||
for it. Yet what a temptation, at certain moments, to turn one’s
|
||
back on this bleak, fleshless world! But this time is ours, and we
|
||
cannot live hating ourselves. It has fallen so low only through the
|
||
excess of its virtues as well as through the extent of its vices. We
|
||
shall fight for the virtue that has a history. What virtue? The horses
|
||
of Patroclus weep for their master killed in battle. All is lost. But
|
||
Achilles resumes the fight, and victory is the outcome, because
|
||
friendship has just been assassinated: friendship is a virtue.
|
||
Admission of ignorance, rejection of fanaticism, the limits of
|
||
the world and of man, the beloved face, and finally beauty—this is
|
||
where we shall be on the side of the Greeks. In a certain sense, the
|
||
direction history will take is not the one we think. It lies in the
|
||
struggle between creation and inquisition. Despite the price which
|
||
artists will pay for their empty hands, we may hope for their
|
||
victory. Once more the philosophy of darkness will break and fade
|
||
away over the dazzling sea. O midday thought, the Trojan war is
|
||
being fought far from the battlefields! Once more the dreadful
|
||
walls of the modern city will fall to deliver up—“soul serene as the
|
||
ocean’s calm”—the beauty of Helen.
|
||
(1948)
|
||
Return To Tipasa
|
||
You have navigated with raging soul far from the paternal
|
||
home, passing beyond the sea’s double rocks, and you now inhabit
|
||
a foreign land.
|
||
—Medea
|
||
For five days rain had been falling ceaselessly on Algiers and
|
||
had finally wet the sea itself. From an apparently inexhaustible
|
||
sky, constant downpours, viscous in their density, streamed down
|
||
upon the gulf. Gray and soft as a huge sponge, the sea rose slowly
|
||
in the ill-defined bay. But the surface of the water seemed almost
|
||
motionless under the steady rain. Only now and then a barely
|
||
perceptible swelling motion would raise above the sea’s surface a
|
||
vague puff of smoke that would come to dock in the harbor, under
|
||
an arc of wet boulevards. The city itself, all its white walls
|
||
dripping, gave off a different steam that went out to meet the first
|
||
steam. Whichever way you turned, you seemed to be breathing
|
||
water, to be drinking the air.
|
||
In front of the soaked sea I walked and waited in that
|
||
December Algiers, which was for me the city of summers. I had
|
||
fled Europe’s night, the winter of faces. But the summer city
|
||
herself had been emptied of her laughter and offered me only bent
|
||
and shining backs. In the evening, in the crudely lighted cafes
|
||
where I took refuge, I read my age in faces I recognized without
|
||
being able to name them. I merely knew that they had been young
|
||
with me and that they were no longer so.
|
||
Yet I persisted without very well knowing what I was waiting
|
||
for, unless perhaps the moment to go back to Tipasa. To be sure, it
|
||
is sheer madness, almost always punished, to return to the sites of
|
||
one’s youth and try to relive at forty what one loved or keenly
|
||
enjoyed at twenty. But I was forewarned of that madness. Once
|
||
already I had returned to Tipasa, soon after those war years that
|
||
marked for me the end of youth. I hoped, I think, to recapture there
|
||
a freedom I could not forget. In that spot, indeed, more than twenty
|
||
years ago, I had spent whole mornings wandering among the ruins,
|
||
breathing in the wormwood, warming myself against the stones,
|
||
discovering little roses, soon plucked of their petals, which outlive
|
||
the spring. Only at noon, at the hour when the cicadas themselves
|
||
fell silent as if overcome, I would flee the greedy glare of an all-
|
||
consuming light. Sometimes at night I would sleep open-eyed
|
||
under a sky dripping with stars. I was alive then. Fifteen years later
|
||
I found my ruins, a few feet from the first waves, I followed the
|
||
streets of the forgotten walled city through fields covered with
|
||
bitter trees, and on the slopes overlooking the hay I still caressed
|
||
the bread-colored columns. But the ruins were now surrounded
|
||
with barbed wire and could be entered only through certain
|
||
openings. It was also forbidden, for reasons which it appears that
|
||
morality approves, to walk there at night; by day one encountered
|
||
an official guardian. It just happened, that morning, that it was
|
||
raining over the whole extent of the ruins.
|
||
Disoriented, walking through the wet, solitary countryside, I
|
||
tried at least to recapture that strength, hitherto always at hand, that
|
||
helps me to accept what is when once I have admitted that I cannot
|
||
change it. And I could not, indeed, reverse the course of time and
|
||
restore to the world the appearance I had loved which had
|
||
disappeared in a day, long before. The second of September 1939,
|
||
in fact, I had not gone to Greece, as I was to do. War, on the
|
||
contrary, had come to us, then it had spread over Greece herself.
|
||
That distance, those years separating the warm ruins from the
|
||
barbed wire were to be found in me, too, that day as I stood before
|
||
the sarcophaguses full of black water or under the sodden
|
||
tamarisks. Originally brought up surrounded by beauty which was
|
||
my only wealth, I had begun in plenty. Then had come the barbed
|
||
wire—I mean tyrannies, war, police forces, the era of revolt. One
|
||
had had to put oneself right with the authorities of night: the day’s
|
||
beauty was but a memory. And in this muddy Tipasa the memory
|
||
itself was becoming dim. It was indeed a question of beauty,
|
||
plenty, or youth! In the light from conflagrations the world had
|
||
suddenly shown its wrinkles and its wounds, old and new. It had
|
||
aged all at once, and we with it. I had come here looking for a
|
||
certain “lift”; but I realized that it inspires only the man who is
|
||
unaware that he is about to launch forward. No love without a little
|
||
innocence. Where was the innocence? Empires were tumbling
|
||
down; nations and men were tearing at one another’s throats; our
|
||
hands were soiled. Originally innocent without knowing it, we
|
||
were now guilty without meaning to be: the mystery was
|
||
increasing with our knowledge. This is why, O mockery, we were
|
||
concerned with morality. Weak and disabled, I was dreaming of
|
||
virtue! In the days of innocence I didn’t even know that morality
|
||
existed. I knew it now, and I was not capable of living up to its
|
||
standard. On the promontory that I used to love, among the wet
|
||
columns of the ruined temple, I seemed to be walking behind
|
||
someone whose steps I could still hear on the stone slabs and
|
||
mosaics but whom I should never again overtake. I went back to
|
||
Paris and remained several years before returning home.
|
||
Yet I obscurely missed something during all those years. When
|
||
one has once had the good luck to love intensely, life is spent in
|
||
trying to recapture that ardor and that illumination. Forsaking
|
||
beauty and the sensual happiness attached to it, exclusively serving
|
||
misfortune, calls for a nobility I lack. But, after all, nothing is true
|
||
that forces one to exclude. Isolated beauty ends up simpering;
|
||
solitary justice ends up oppressing. Whoever aims to serve one
|
||
exclusive of the other serves no one, not even himself, and
|
||
eventually serves injustice twice. A day comes when, thanks to
|
||
rigidity, nothing causes wonder any more, everything is known,
|
||
and life is spent in beginning over again. These are the days of
|
||
exile, of desiccated life, of dead souls. To come alive again, one
|
||
needs a special grace, self-forgetfulness, or a homeland. Certain
|
||
mornings, on turning a corner, a delightful dew falls on the heart
|
||
and then evaporates. But its coolness remains, and this is what the
|
||
heart requires always. I had to set out again.
|
||
And in Algiers a second time, still walking under the same
|
||
downpour which seemed not to have ceased since a departure I had
|
||
thought definitive, amid the same vast melancholy smelling of rain
|
||
and sea, despite this misty sky, these backs fleeing under the
|
||
shower, these cafes whose sulphureous light distorted faces, I
|
||
persisted in hoping. Didn’t I know, besides, that Algiers rains,
|
||
despite their appearance of never meaning to end, nonetheless stop
|
||
in an instant, like those streams in my country which rise in two
|
||
hours, lay waste acres of land, and suddenly dry up? One evening,
|
||
in fact, the rain ceased. I waited one night more. A limpid morning
|
||
rose, dazzling, over the pure sea. From the sky, fresh as a daisy,
|
||
washed over and over again by the rains, reduced by these repeated
|
||
washings to its finest and clearest texture, emanated a vibrant light
|
||
that gave to each house and each tree a sharp outline, an astonished
|
||
newness. In the world’s morning the earth must have sprung forth
|
||
in such a light. I again took the road for Tipasa.
|
||
For me there is not a single one of those sixty-nine kilometers
|
||
that is not filled with memories and sensations. Turbulent
|
||
childhood, adolescent daydreams in the drone of the bus’s motor,
|
||
mornings, unspoiled girls, beaches, young muscles always at the
|
||
peak of their effort, evening’s slight anxiety in a sixteen-year-old
|
||
heart, lust for life, fame, and ever the same sky throughout the
|
||
years, unfailing in strength and light, itself insatiable, consuming
|
||
one by one over a period of months the victims stretched out in the
|
||
form of crosses on the beach at the deathlike hour of noon. Always
|
||
the same sea, too, almost impalpable in the morning light, which I
|
||
again saw on the horizon as soon as the road, leaving the Sahel and
|
||
its bronze-colored vineyards, sloped down toward the coast. But I
|
||
did not stop to look at it. I wanted to see again the Chenoua, that
|
||
solid, heavy mountain cut out of a single block of stone, which
|
||
borders the bay of Tipasa to the west before dropping down into
|
||
the sea itself. It is seen from a distance, long before arriving, a
|
||
light, blue haze still confused with the sky. But gradually it is
|
||
condensed, as you advance toward it, until it takes on the color of
|
||
the surrounding waters, a huge motionless wave whose amazing
|
||
leap upward has been brutally solidified above the sea calmed all
|
||
at once. Still nearer, almost at the gates of Tipasa, here is its
|
||
frowning bulk, brown and green, here is the old mossy god that
|
||
nothing will ever shake, a refuge and harbor for its sons, of whom I
|
||
am one.
|
||
While watching it I finally got through the barbed wire and
|
||
found myself among the ruins. And under the glorious December
|
||
light, as happens but once or twice in lives which ever after can
|
||
consider themselves favored to the full, I found exactly what I had
|
||
come seeking, what, despite the era and the world, was offered me,
|
||
truly to me alone, in that forsaken nature. From the forum strewn
|
||
with olives could be seen the village down below. No sound came
|
||
from it; wisps of smoke rose in the limpid air. The sea likewise
|
||
was silent as if smothered under the unbroken shower of dazzling,
|
||
cold light. From the Chenoua a distant cock’s crow alone
|
||
celebrated the day’s fragile glory. In the direction of the ruins, as
|
||
far as the eye could see, there was nothing but pock-marked stones
|
||
and wormwood, trees and perfect columns in the transparence of
|
||
the crystalline air. It seemed as if the morning were stabilized, the
|
||
sun stopped for an incalculable moment. In this light and this
|
||
silence, years of wrath and night melted slowly away. I listened to
|
||
an almost forgotten sound within myself as if my heart, long
|
||
stopped, were calmly beginning to beat again. And awake now, I
|
||
recognized one by one the imperceptible sounds of which the
|
||
silence was made up: the figured bass of the birds, the sea’s faint,
|
||
brief sighs at the foot of the rocks, the vibration of the trees, the
|
||
blind singing of the columns, the rustling of the wormwood plants,
|
||
the furtive lizards. I heard that; I also listened to the happy torrents
|
||
rising within me. It seemed to me that I had at last come to harbor,
|
||
for a moment at least, and that henceforth that moment would be
|
||
endless. But soon after, the sun rose visibly a degree in the sky. A
|
||
magpie preluded briefly, and at once, from all directions, birds’
|
||
songs burst out with energy, jubilation, joyful discordance, and
|
||
infinite rapture. The day started up again. It was to carry me to
|
||
evening.
|
||
At noon on the half-sandy slopes covered with heliotropes like
|
||
a foam left by the furious waves of the last few days as they
|
||
withdrew, I watched the sea barely swelling at that hour with an
|
||
exhausted motion, and I satisfied the two thirsts one cannot long
|
||
neglect without drying up—I mean loving and admiring. For there
|
||
is merely bad luck in not being loved; there is misfortune in not
|
||
loving. All of us, today, are dying of this misfortune. For violence
|
||
and hatred dry up the heart itself; the long fight for justice exhausts
|
||
the love that nevertheless gave birth to it. In the clamor in which
|
||
we live, love is impossible and justice does not suffice. This is why
|
||
Europe hates daylight and is only able to set injustice up against
|
||
injustice. But in order to keep justice from shriveling up like a
|
||
beautiful orange fruit containing nothing but a bitter, dry pulp, I
|
||
discovered once more at Tipasa that one must keep intact in
|
||
oneself a freshness, a cool wellspring of joy, love the day that
|
||
escapes injustice, and return to combat having won that light. Here
|
||
I recaptured the former beauty, a young sky, and I measured my
|
||
luck, realizing at last that in the worst years of our madness the
|
||
memory of that sky had never left me. This was what in the end
|
||
had kept me from despairing. I had always known that the ruins of
|
||
Tipasa were younger than our new constructions or our bomb
|
||
damage. There the world began over again every day in an ever
|
||
new light. O light! This is the cry of all the characters of ancient
|
||
drama brought face to face with their fate. This last resort was
|
||
ours, too, and I knew it now. In the middle of winter I at last
|
||
discovered that there was in me an invincible summer.
|
||
* * *
|
||
I have again left Tipasa; I have returned to Europe and its
|
||
struggles. But the memory of that day still uplifts me and helps me
|
||
to welcome equally what delights and what crushes. In the difficult
|
||
hour we are living, what else can I desire than to exclude nothing
|
||
and to learn how to braid with white thread and black thread a
|
||
single cord stretched to the breaking-point? In everything I have
|
||
done or said up to now, I seem to recognize these two forces, even
|
||
when they work at cross-purposes. I have not been able to disown
|
||
the light into which I was born and yet I have not wanted to reject
|
||
the servitudes of this time. It would be too easy to contrast here
|
||
with the sweet name of Tipasa other more sonorous and crueler
|
||
names. For men of today there is an inner way, which I know well
|
||
from having taken it in both directions, leading from the spiritual
|
||
hilltops to the capitals of crime. And doubtless one can always rest,
|
||
fall asleep on the hilltop or board with crime. But if one forgoes a
|
||
part of what is, one must forgo being oneself; one must forgo
|
||
living or loving otherwise than by proxy. There is thus a will to
|
||
live without rejecting anything of life, which is the virtue I honor
|
||
most in this world. From time to time, at least, it is true that I
|
||
should like to have practiced it. Inasmuch as few epochs require as
|
||
much as ours that one should be equal to the best as to the worst, I
|
||
should like, indeed, to shirk nothing and to keep faithfully a double
|
||
memory. Yes, there is beauty and there are the humiliated.
|
||
Whatever may be the difficulties of the undertaking, I should like
|
||
never to be unfaithful either to one or to the others.
|
||
But this still resembles a moral code, and we live for something
|
||
that goes farther than morality. If we could only name it, what
|
||
silence! On the hill of Sainte-Salsa, to the east of Tipasa, the
|
||
evening is inhabited. It is still light, to tell the truth, but in this light
|
||
an almost invisible fading announces the day’s end. A wind rises,
|
||
young like the night, and suddenly the waveless sea chooses a
|
||
direction and flows like a great barren river from one end of the
|
||
horizon to the other. The sky darkens. Then begins the mystery, the
|
||
gods of night, the beyond-pleasure. But how to translate this? The
|
||
little coin I am carrying away from here has a visible surface, a
|
||
woman’s beautiful face which repeats to me all I have learned in
|
||
this day, and a worn surface which I feel under my fingers during
|
||
the return. What can that lipless mouth be saying, except what I am
|
||
told by another mysterious voice, within me, which every day
|
||
informs me of my ignorance and my happiness:
|
||
“The secret I am seeking lies hidden in a valley full of olive
|
||
trees, under the grass and the cold violets, around an old house that
|
||
smells of wood smoke. For more than twenty years I rambled over
|
||
that valley and others resembling it, I questioned mute goatherds, I
|
||
knocked at the door of deserted ruins. Occasionally, at the moment
|
||
of the first star in the still bright sky, under a shower of
|
||
shimmering light, I thought I knew. I did know, in truth. I still
|
||
know, perhaps. But no one wants any of this secret; I don’t want
|
||
any myself, doubtless; and I cannot stand apart from my people. I
|
||
live in my family, which thinks it rules over rich and hideous cities
|
||
built of stones and mists. Day and night it speaks up, and
|
||
everything bows before it, which bows before nothing: it is deaf to
|
||
all secrets. Its power that carries me bores me, nevertheless, and on
|
||
occasion its shouts weary me. But its misfortune is mine, and we
|
||
are of the same blood. A cripple, likewise, an accomplice and
|
||
noisy, have I not shouted among the stones? Consequently, I strive
|
||
to forget, I walk in our cities of iron and fire, I smile bravely at the
|
||
night, I hail the storms, I shall be faithful. I have forgotten, in truth:
|
||
active and deaf, henceforth. But perhaps someday, when we are
|
||
ready to die of exhaustion and ignorance, I shall be able to disown
|
||
our garish tombs and go and stretch out in the valley, under the
|
||
same light, and learn for the last time what I know.”
|
||
(1952)
|
||
The Artist And His Time
|
||
I. As an artist, have you chosen the role of witness?
|
||
This would take considerable presumption or a vocation I lack.
|
||
Personally I don’t ask for any role and I have but one real vocation.
|
||
As a man, I have a preference for happiness; as an artist, it seems
|
||
to me that I still have characters to bring to life without the help of
|
||
wars or of law-courts. But I have been sought out, as each
|
||
individual has been sought out. Artists of the past could at least
|
||
keep silent in the face of tyranny. The tyrannies of today are
|
||
improved; they no longer admit of silence or neutrality. One has to
|
||
take a stand, be either for or against. Well, in that case, I am
|
||
against. But this does not amount to choosing the comfortable role
|
||
of witness. It is merely accepting the time as it is, minding one’s
|
||
own business, in short. Moreover, you are forgetting that today
|
||
judges, accused, and witnesses exchange positions with exemplary
|
||
rapidity. My choice, if you think I am making one, would at least
|
||
be never to sit on a judge’s bench, or beneath it, like so many of
|
||
our philosophers. Aside from that, there is no dearth of
|
||
opportunities for action, in the relative. Trade-unionism is today
|
||
the first, and the most fruitful among them.
|
||
II. Is not the quixotism that has been criticized in your recent
|
||
works an idealistic and romantic definition of the artist’s role?
|
||
However words are perverted, they provisionally keep their
|
||
meaning. And it is clear to me that the romantic is the one who
|
||
chooses the perpetual motion of history, the grandiose epic, and the
|
||
announcement of a miraculous event at the end of time. If I have
|
||
tried to define something, it is, on the contrary, simply the common
|
||
existence of history and of man, everyday life with the most
|
||
possible light thrown upon it, the dogged struggle against one’s
|
||
own degradation and that of others.
|
||
It is likewise idealism, and of the worse kind, to end up by
|
||
hanging all action and all truth on a meaning of history that is not
|
||
implicit in events and that, in any case, implies a mythical aim.
|
||
Would it therefore be realism to take as the laws of history the
|
||
future—in other words, just what is not yet history, something of
|
||
whose nature we know nothing?
|
||
It seems to me, on the contrary, that I am arguing in favor of a
|
||
true realism against a mythology that is both illogical and deadly,
|
||
and against romantic nihilism whether it be bourgeois or allegedly
|
||
revolutionary. To tell the truth, far from being romantic, I believe
|
||
in the necessity of a rule and an order. I merely say that there can
|
||
be no question of just any rule whatsoever. And that it would be
|
||
surprising if the rule we need were given us by this disordered
|
||
society, or, on the other hand, by those doctrinaires who declare
|
||
themselves liberated from all rules and all scruples.
|
||
III. The Marxists and their followers likewise think they are
|
||
humanists. But for them human nature will be formed in the
|
||
classless society of the future.
|
||
To begin with, this proves that they reject at the present
|
||
moment what we all are: those humanists are accusers of man.
|
||
How can we be surprised that such a claim should have developed
|
||
in the world of court trials? They reject the man of today in the
|
||
name of the man of the future. That claim is religious in nature.
|
||
Why should it be more justified than the one which announces the
|
||
kingdom of heaven to come? In reality the end of history cannot
|
||
have, within the limits of our condition, any definable significance.
|
||
It can only be the object of a faith and of a new mystification. A
|
||
mystification that today is no less great than the one that of old
|
||
based colonial oppression on the necessity of saving the souls of
|
||
infidels.
|
||
IV. Is not that what in reality separates you from the
|
||
intellectuals of the left?
|
||
You mean that is what separates those intellectuals from the
|
||
left? Traditionally the left has always been at war against injustice,
|
||
obscurantism, and oppression. It always thought that those
|
||
phenomena were interdependent. The idea that obscurantism can
|
||
lead to justice, the national interest to liberty, is quite recent. The
|
||
truth is that certain intellectuals of the left (not all, fortunately) are
|
||
today hypnotized by force and efficacy as our intellectuals of the
|
||
right were before and during the war. Their attitudes are different,
|
||
but the act of resignation is the same. The first wanted to be
|
||
realistic nationalists; the second want to be realistic socialists. In
|
||
the end they betray nationalism and socialism alike in the name of
|
||
a realism henceforth without content and adored as a pure, and
|
||
illusory, technique of efficacy.
|
||
This is a temptation that can, after all, be understood. But still,
|
||
however the question is looked at, the new position of the people
|
||
who call themselves, or think themselves, leftists consists in
|
||
saying: certain oppressions are justifiable because they follow the
|
||
direction, which cannot be justified, of history. Hence there are
|
||
presumably privileged executioners, and privileged by nothing.
|
||
This is about what was said in another context by Joseph de
|
||
Maistre, who has never been taken for an incendiary. But this is a
|
||
thesis which, personally, I shall always reject. Allow me to set up
|
||
against it the traditional point of view of what has been hitherto
|
||
called the left: all executioners are of the same family.
|
||
V. What can the artist do in the world of today?
|
||
He is not asked either to write about co-operatives or,
|
||
conversely, to lull to sleep in himself the sufferings endured by
|
||
others throughout history. And since you have asked me to speak
|
||
personally, I am going to do so as simply as I can. Considered as
|
||
artists, we perhaps have no need to interfere in the affairs of the
|
||
world. But considered as men, yes. The miner who is exploited or
|
||
shot down, the slaves in the camps, those in the colonies, the
|
||
legions of persecuted throughout the world—they need all those
|
||
who can speak to communicate their silence and to keep in touch
|
||
with them. I have not written, day after day, fighting articles and
|
||
texts, I have not taken part in the common struggles because I
|
||
desire the world to be covered with Greek statues and
|
||
masterpieces. The man who has such a desire does exist in me.
|
||
Except that he has something better to do in trying to instill life
|
||
into the creatures of his imagination. But from my first articles to
|
||
my latest book I have written so much, and perhaps too much, only
|
||
because I cannot keep from being drawn toward everyday life,
|
||
toward those, whoever they may be, who are humiliated and
|
||
debased. They need to hope, and if all keep silent or if they are
|
||
given a choice between two kinds of humiliation, they will be
|
||
forever deprived of hope and we with them. It seems to me
|
||
impossible to endure that idea, nor can he who cannot endure it lie
|
||
down to sleep in his tower. Not through virtue, as you see, but
|
||
through a sort of almost organic intolerance, which you feel or do
|
||
not feel. Indeed, I see many who fail to feel it, but I cannot envy
|
||
their sleep. This does not mean, however, that we must sacrifice
|
||
our artist’s nature to some social preaching or other. I have said
|
||
elsewhere why the artist was more than ever necessary. But if we
|
||
intervene as men, that experience will have an effect upon our
|
||
language. And if we are not artists in our language first of all, what
|
||
sort of artists are we? Even if, militants in our lives, we speak in
|
||
our works of deserts and of selfish love, the mere fact that our lives
|
||
are militant causes a special tone of voice to people with men that
|
||
desert and that love. I shall certainly not choose the moment when
|
||
we are beginning to leave nihilism behind to stupidly deny the
|
||
values of creation in favor of the values of humanity, or vice versa.
|
||
In my mind neither one is ever separated from the other and I
|
||
measure the greatness of an artist (Moliere, Tolstoy, Melville) by
|
||
the balance he managed to maintain between the two. Today, under
|
||
the pressure of events, we are obliged to transport that tension into
|
||
our lives likewise. This is why so many artists, bending under the
|
||
burden, take refuge in the ivory tower or, conversely, in the social
|
||
church. But as for me, I see in both choices a like act of
|
||
resignation. We must simultaneously serve suffering and beauty.
|
||
The long patience, “The strength, the secret cunning such service
|
||
calls for are the virtues that establish the very renascence we need.
|
||
One word more. This undertaking, I know, cannot be
|
||
accomplished without dangers and bitterness. We must accept the
|
||
dangers: the era of chairbound artists is over. But we must reject
|
||
the bitterness. One of the temptations of the artist is to believe
|
||
himself solitary, and in truth he bears this shouted at him with a
|
||
certain base delight. But this is not true. He stands in the midst of
|
||
all, in the same rank, neither higher nor lower, with all those who
|
||
are working and struggling. His very vocation, in the face of
|
||
oppression, is to open the prisons and to give a voice to the
|
||
sorrows and joys of all. This is where art, against its enemies,
|
||
justifies itself by proving precisely that it is no one’s enemy. By
|
||
itself art could probably not produce the renascence which implies
|
||
justice and liberty. But without it, that renascence would be
|
||
without forms and, consequently, would be nothing. Without
|
||
culture, and the relative freedom it implies, society, even when
|
||
perfect, is but a jungle. This is why any authentic creation is a gift
|
||
to the future.
|
||
(1953) |